AustLII Home | Databases | WorldLII | Search | Feedback

Melbourne University Law Review

Melbourne Law School
You are here:  AustLII >> Databases >> Melbourne University Law Review >> 2009 >> [2009] MelbULawRw 19

Database Search | Name Search | Recent Articles | Noteup | LawCite | Help

Terry, Andrew; Lernia, Cary Di --- "Franchising and the Quest for the Holy Grail: Good Faith or Good Intentions?" [2009] MelbULawRw 19; (2009) 33(2) Melbourne University Law Review 542


FRANCHISING AND THE QUEST FOR THE HOLY GRAIL: GOOD FAITH OR GOOD INTENTIONS?

ANDREW TERRY[*] AND CARY DI LERNIA[†]

[The recent Opportunity Not Opportunism: Improving Conduct in Australian Franchising report by the Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services (released December 2008) concluded that, while the prior disclosure obligations of Australia’s regulatory instrument for franchising (the Franchising Code of Conduct) are for the most part adequately addressed, there remain concerns because of ‘the continuing absence of an explicit overarching standard of conduct for parties entering a franchise agreement’. The Joint Committee recommended that the optimal way to address this concern, and thereby provide a deterrent against opportunistic conduct in the franchising sector, was ‘to explicitly incorporate, in its simplest form, the existing and widely accepted implied duty of parties to a franchise agreement to act in good faith’. This article analyses the scope and content of the existing implied obligation of good faith at common law and considers the implications for the franchise sector of a good faith obligation, were one to be incorporated into the Code.]

I INTRODUCTION

In the time of the legendary King Arthur, the quest for the Holy Grail was the highest spiritual pursuit for a knight. Today, franchise reformers search for their own Holy Grail — a convenient formula to deliver balance and equity to the franchise relationship, which is commonly characterised by both power and information imbalances.[1] In Australia, there is a growing body of opinion that ‘good faith’ is the Holy Grail for the franchise sector and that a requirement that the parties to a franchise agreement act in good faith should be imposed[2] by amendment of the current regulatory instrument, the Franchising Code of Conduct (‘Code’)[3] (which is prescribed under pt IVB of the Trade Practices Act 1974 (Cth) as a mandatory industry code).[4]

While ‘good faith’ is a concept familiar to civil law jurisdictions,[5] its application in common law jurisdictions is relatively new and is characterised by ‘twists and turns in [its] ongoing development’.[6] Brereton J recently observed that ‘the implication of a term … [of] good faith does not fit neatly into the structure of Australian contract law’.[7] In the United States of America, the Uniform Commercial Code provides in § 1-304 that ‘[e]very contract or duty within [the Uniform Commercial Code] imposes an obligation of good faith in its performance and enforcement.’[8] Franchising has generally been held to be subject to this standard.[9] An implied covenant of good faith and fair dealing is also articulated in § 205 of the Restatement (Second) of Contracts.[10] Thomas Pitegoff and Michael Garner nevertheless suggest that:

Although the ‘covenant’ of good faith and fair dealing probably is law in most jurisdictions, there are very few cases where that principle, by itself, has led to a ruling favourable to a franchisee. Several courts have held that no cause of action exists for an alleged violation of the covenant in the absence of an allegation of violation in bad faith of an express term of the agreement.[11]

In the United Kingdom, franchise agreements are not subject to overarching and overriding duties of good faith under the common law.[12] The application of ‘non-derogation from grant’ property law principles in a franchising context in Fleet Mobile Tyres Ltd v Stone (‘Stone’)[13] nevertheless suggests that ‘good faith’ may emerge under another guise. In Canada, a duty of good faith exists at common law in the context of a franchise relationship[14] and is codified in the franchise laws of Alberta, New Brunswick, Ontario, and Prince Edward Island.[15]

Australia has had four government inquiries into the franchise sector and its regulation in the last two years.[16]

Three of the four reports recommended the introduction of a good faith obligation.

The Review of the Disclosure Provisions of the Franchising Code of Conduct (‘Matthews Report’) of October 2006 noted that ‘interdependency between franchisors and franchisees is fundamental to the franchise sector’ and

consider[ed] that recognition in the Code of a concept of good faith and fair dealing would provide positive reinforcement to the development of improved relationships and dealings between franchisors, franchisees and prospective franchisees.[17]

The report recommended that a ‘statement obligating franchisors, franchisees and prospective franchisees to act towards each other fairly and in good faith be developed for inclusion in Part 1 of the Code.’[18] The government’s response in February 2007 was parsimonious. It ‘agree[d] with the intention’ that franchise participants ‘act towards each other fairly and in good faith’ but simply noted that s 51AC of the Trade Practices Act 1974 (Cth) — the business unconscionability provision — ‘includes “good faith” as a factor that can be taken into account when determining’ whether a party has acted unconscionably.[19]

The Final Report Franchises (‘South Australian Report’) was of the opinion that ‘there currently exist unacceptable limits on the ability of the franchisees to seek redress in cases where franchisors abuse their contractual discretions and powers.’[20]

The Economic and Finance Committee of the South Australian Parliament recommended amending the Code by inserting a provision imposing ‘a duty to act in accordance with good faith and fair dealing [on] each party of the franchise relationship.’[21]

The latest and most influential report[22]

Opportunity Not Opportunism: Improving Conduct in Australian Franchising (‘Opportunity Not Opportunism Report’) by the Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services (released December 2008) — concluded that, while the Code’s prior disclosure obligations ‘have been, for the most part, adequately addressed by past inquiries, there remains concern … [because of] the continuing absence of an explicit overarching standard of conduct for parties entering a franchising agreement.’[23] The report noted that:

the interdependent nature of the franchise relationship leaves the parties to the agreement vulnerable to opportunistic conduct by either franchisors or franchisees. Franchisee opportunism may take the form of free riding, unauthorised use of franchisors’ intellectual property rights, underperformance, or failure to accurately disclose income. However, the franchisor’s control over the provisions in the contract enables franchisors to address opportunistic behaviour of this kind by enforcing the terms of the franchise agreement.
Franchisor opportunism has been described as ‘predatory conduct and strong arm tactics by franchisors’ involving the exploitation of a pre-existing power relationship between the franchising parties, which makes the franchisee ‘vulnerable or economically captive to the demands of the franchisor’. There is an inherent and necessary imbalance of power in franchise agreements in favour of the franchisor, but abuse of this power can lead to opportunistic practices including encroachment, kickbacks, churning, non-renewal, transfer, termination at will, and unreasonable unilateral variations to the agreement.[24]

The Joint Committee’s conclusion was

that the optimal way to provide a deterrent against opportunistic conduct in the franchising sector is to explicitly incorporate, in its simplest form, the existing and widely accepted implied duty of parties to a franchise agreement to act in good faith.[25]

The Joint Committee recommended that the following new clause be inserted into the Code:

6 Standard of Conduct
Franchisors, franchisees and prospective franchisees shall act in good faith in relation to all aspects of a franchise agreement.[26]

This article examines the common law developments in relation to an implied obligation of good faith, the elusive nature of its scope and meaning, and the implications for the franchise sector if a good faith obligation were to be enacted.

II GOOD FAITH AND THE FRANCHISE RELATIONSHIP

Outside legislative direction, an obligation of good faith can arise in a franchise agreement in three ways — as an express term of the contract,[27] as a term implied in fact on an ad hoc basis to give business efficacy to the contract,[28] or as a term implied in law as a necessary incident of the contract.[29] A fourth possibility is that the obligation of good faith is a principle of construction which is ‘inherent in all common law contract principles,’ meaning that the implication of ‘independent term[s] requiring good faith is unnecessary and a retrograde step.’[30] This argument was strongly contested by Bergin J in Insight Oceania Pty Ltd v Philips Electronics Australia Ltd (‘Insight Oceana’) on the basis that ‘[i]t is erroneous to suggest that the modern approach to the construction of contracts, whether one refers to it as commercial construction or otherwise, is driven by a concern “to ensure good faith”.’[31] Bergin J did not refer to, but is strongly supported by, the decision of the Court of Appeal of New South Wales in Vodafone Pacific Ltd v Mobile Innovations Ltd (‘Vodafone’), which held that an obligation of good faith is implied in law ‘and does not proceed on a fiction that an intention of the parties is being found by a process of construction.’[32]

There is increasing judicial support, albeit not at the highest levels of the judicial hierarchies, for a term of good faith to be implied in law as a necessary incident of a commercial contract.[33] In 1999, Finkelstein J of the Federal Court of Australia stated in Garry Rogers Motors (Aust) Pty Ltd v Subaru (Aust) Pty Ltd (‘Garry Rogers’) that ‘in appropriate contracts, perhaps even in all commercial contracts, such a term will ordinarily be implied; not as an ad hoc term (based on the presumed intention of the parties) but as a legal incident of the relationship’.[34] In 2001, the NSW Court of Appeal in Burger King Corporation v Hungry Jack’s Pty Ltd (‘Burger King (Appeal)’) was also of the opinion that a duty of good faith should be implied in law.[35] In Overlook Management BV v Foxtel Management Pty Ltd (‘Overlook’), Barrett J in the Supreme Court of New South Wales went so far as to state that ‘a term requiring the exercise of good faith in the performance’ of a commercial contract ‘is now in [NSW] a legal incident of every such contract’.[36]

This view has wide — albeit not unanimous — support throughout Australia. Despite the support of the NSW Court of Appeal in Burger King (Appeal), a differently constituted Court of Appeal[37] in Vodafone stated that it did ‘not think the law has yet gone so far as to say that commercial contracts are a class of contracts carrying the implied terms as a legal incident, and the width and indeterminacy of the class of contracts would make it a large step.’[38]

In Esso Australia Resources Pty Ltd v Southern Pacific Petroleum NL (‘Esso Australia’),[39] the Court of Appeal of Victoria expressed reluctance — or, in the words of Dodds-Streeton J in a later case, ‘evinced a reserved approach’[40] — to endorsing the implication of a term of good faith as a legal incident of commercial contracts. Buchanan JA (with whom Warren CJ and Osborn AJA agreed) expressed a preference for ‘ad hoc implication meeting the tests laid down in BP Refinery (Westernport) Pty Ltd v Shire of Hastings,[41] rather than implication as a matter of law creating a legal incident of contracts of a certain type.’[42] Buchanan JA nevertheless qualified his reservations:

I am reluctant to conclude that commercial contracts are a class of contracts carrying an implied term of good faith as a legal incident, so that an obligation of good faith applies indiscriminately to all the rights and powers conferred by a commercial contract. It may, however, be appropriate in a particular case to import such an obligation to protect a vulnerable party from exploitative conduct which subverts the original purpose for which the contract was made.[43]

Franchising is of course an example of a commercial contract in which a vulnerable party may be susceptible to exploitative conduct.[44]

Warren CJ, in the same case, noted that, even if a term of good faith could arise as legal incident of a commercial contract, it would not arise in every case:

Ultimately, the interests of certainty in contractual activity should be interfered with only when the relationship between the parties is unbalanced and one party is at a substantial disadvantage, or is particularly vulnerable in the prevailing context. Where commercial leviathans are contractually engaged, it is difficult to see that a duty of good faith will arise, leaving aside duties that might arise in a fiduciary relationship. If one party to a contract is more shrewd, more cunning and out-manoeuvres the other contracting party who did not suffer a disadvantage and who was not vulnerable, it is difficult to see why the latter should have greater protection than that provided by the law of contract.[45]

These issues are yet to be addressed by the High Court of Australia. In Royal Botanic Gardens and Domain Trust v South Sydney City Council (‘Royal Botanic Gardens’), questions were raised by the ‘rather far-reaching contentions of the appellant’ as to

whether both in performing obligations and exercising rights under a contract, all parties owe to one another a duty of good faith; and, the extent to which, if such were to be the law, a duty of good faith might deny a party an opportunistic or commercial exercise of an otherwise lawful commercial right.[46]

Unfortunately for the development of the law in this difficult area, it was unnecessary in the appeal for the High Court to explore these questions further. Kirby J nevertheless observed that:

The court was taken to case law both in [Australia] and overseas as well as to academic commentary to demonstrate a growing tendency to imply into private contractual dealings a covenant of good faith and fair dealing. As expressed in some United States decisions, this is a principle that is not confined to an obligation to exercise express contractual powers fairly and reasonably. In some parts of the United States, the obligation has been accepted as a general implied contractual term in its own right.[47]

Although it was not necessary in the appeal to explore these issues, Kirby J does not provide great comfort to those who argue that good faith imposes an overarching ethical obligation:

in Australia, such an implied term appears to conflict with fundamental notions of caveat emptor that are inherent (statute and equitable intervention apart) in common law conceptions of economic freedom. It also appears to be inconsistent with the law as it has developed in this country in respect of the introduction of implied terms into written contracts which the parties have omitted to include.[48]

Although the propositions supporting the implication of an obligation of good faith as a necessary incident of the contract have generally been expressed in relation to ‘commercial contracts’, the case for implication of a term as a necessary incident of franchise contracts is much stronger given their relational nature. In the academic literature, the case for the implication of good faith is based on the recognition of the special circumstances present in relational contracts.[49]

In one of the very few judicial references to ‘relational contracts’ in Australasia, a New Zealand appellate judge described such contracts in these terms:

In essence, relational contracts recognise the existence of a business relationship between the parties and the need to maintain that relationship; the difficulty of reducing important terms to well-defined obligations; the impossibility of foretelling all the events which may impinge upon the contract; the need to adjust the relationship over time to provide for unforeseen factors or contingencies which cannot readily be provided for in advance; the commitment, likely to be extensive, which one party must make to the other, including significant investment; and that they are in an economic sense likely to be incomplete in failing to allocate, or allocate optimally, the risk between the parties in the event of certain future contingencies. …
Consequently, a relational contract is one which involves not merely an exchange but a relationship between the contractual parties. The parties are not ‘strangers’ in the accepted sense and much of their interaction takes place ‘off the contract’ requiring a deliberate measure of communication, cooperation, and predictable performance based on mutual trust and confidence. Expectations of loyalty and interdependence mark the formation of the contract and become the basis for the rational economic planning of the parties.[50]

In the academic literature, the ‘doctrinal tool’ relied on ‘to bring the resolution of franchise contract disputes into line with the realities of the franchise relation[ship]’ is invariably the implied term of good faith.[51]

Perhaps surprisingly, the express judicial pronouncements stating that good faith is a necessary incident of a ‘commercial contract’ are not supported by any doctrinal underpinning, although it has been argued that a relational ‘vibe’, albeit unexpressed and unacknowledged, lurks not far below the surface of the judgments.[52]

Unlike classical, discrete ‘spot … contracts’,[53] which might be seen as ‘episodic arm-wrestles for economic advantage’,[54] many modern contractual arrangements involve ‘co-operative ventures, based on interpersonal relationships in which many of the important undertakings remain unspecified.’[55] The franchise contract enshrines such a relationship. In the typical business-format franchise agreement, relational considerations feature prominently. As Gillian Hadfield argues convincingly, franchising exists in a ‘world of contractual incompleteness and relational complexity’.[56]

Elizabeth Spencer notes that in franchise relationships the unequal bargaining power and lack of negotiation of the standard form, combined with the relational contract’s reliance on flexibility and trust, strongly reinforce the imbalance of power.[57] But while the categorisation of franchising as a relational contract seems straightforward, the legal consequences that follow from this categorisation are highly controversial. Hadfield argues that the point of departure from traditional contract law is that ‘when a contract is embedded within an identifiable relationship, such as the franchise relationship, contractual obligations are often modified, supplemented or completely supplanted by the norms of the ongoing relation.’[58]

The extent to which these commercial realities of the franchise relationship should be accommodated legally, and whether good faith is the appropriate doctrine through which to do so, thus pose a challenge for the courts and legislators alike.

III GOOD FAITH AND RELATED DOCTRINES

The idea of ‘good faith’ as a guiding principle permeates several accepted legal duties and concepts. The common law duty to cooperate, the doctrine of non-derogation from grant and the unconscionability regime may be argued to cover the field to such a degree that a separate concept of good faith is an unnecessary addition to Australian contract law. Further, as Gummow J stated in Service Station Association Ltd v Berg Bennett & Associates Pty Ltd (in relation to specific equitable interventions in Anglo-Australian contract law where notions of good conscience play a part), ‘it requires a leap of faith to translate these well-established doctrines and remedies into a new term as to the quality of contractual performance, implied by law.’[59]

A The Common Law Duty to Cooperate

John Carter, Elisabeth Peden and Greg Tolhurst — critics of the recognition of a separate implied duty of good faith at common law — argue that ‘[g]ood faith is inherent in all common law contract principles, and any attempt to imply an independent term requiring good faith is unnecessary and a retrograde step.’[60]

Peden argues that good faith is simply a principle which infuses contract law by requiring parties to do all that is reasonably necessary to facilitate performance of a contract:

‘Cooperation’ is sometimes seen as equivalent to ‘good faith’, and this seems appropriate. The effect of requiring cooperation often overlaps with what is trying to be achieved by the newly created obligation of ‘good faith’. Cooperation (or good faith, if that term is preferred) basically must embrace a duty to act honestly and a duty to have regard to the legitimate interests of the other party.[61]

In Insight Oceania, Bergin J was dismissive of this approach, arguing that ‘[i]f the authors did intend to convey that the parties to every contract are contractually bound to act in good faith, it is not consistent with the state of the present law’.[62] A review of the case law nevertheless provides some support for Peden’s view that good faith as it has been applied in the cases often overlaps with an approach based on the undisputed duty of cooperation and that cooperation could have achieved the same result without recourse to an undefined standard of good faith.[63]

However, the question as to whether the duty to cooperate achieves the goals espoused by proponents of good faith as a separate duty must still be asked.

In the oft-cited case of Mackay v Dick, Lord Blackburn stated that:

where in a written contract it appears that both parties have agreed that something shall be done, which cannot effectually be done unless both concur in doing it, the construction of the contract is that each agrees to do all that is necessary to be done on his part for the carrying out of that thing, though there may be no express words to that effect. What is the part of each must depend on circumstances.[64]

Griffith CJ in Butt v M’Donald restated Lord Blackburn’s pronouncement as follows:

It is a general rule applicable to every contract that each party agrees, by implication, to do all such things as are necessary on his part to enable the other party to have the benefit of the contract.[65]

Cooperation appears to require a commitment only to the terms of the contract and whatever lies pregnant within them for the purpose of performance; it does not necessarily require concern to be had for any of the other party’s legitimate interests or expectations that, due to their nature, might not have been expressed in a standard form contract or that may have developed over time without their reduction into certain contractual terms. Because the duty to cooperate operates in the context of the terms of the contract, there is no scope for it to create an independent source of rights (which the proponents of good faith would require).

For these reasons, a requirement of good faith may be thought to hold some promise in bringing balance to the negative potentialities of the franchise relationship, as it may take account of broader concerns beyond the hard terms of a contract. However, the simple duty to cooperate might fail to assist a party to a franchise agreement except in clear cut cases of contractual evasion, frustration and non-performance. This is especially so if an experienced franchisor leaves nothing for the duty of cooperation to work on to the franchisee’s benefit in a standard form contract weighted in favour of and intentionally silent about the responsibilities of the franchisor.

B Non-Derogation from Grant

In Birmingham, Dudley & District Banking Co v Ross, Bowen LJ said that the principle that a grantor must not derogate from a grant made appeared to be ‘as old, I will not say as the hills, but as old as the Year Books, and a great deal older.’[66] In Molton Builders Ltd v City of Westminster London Borough Council, Lord Denning MR commented that non-derogation from grant

is a general principle of law that, if one man agrees to confer a particular benefit on another, he must not do anything which substantially deprives the other of the enjoyment of that benefit: because that would be to take away with one hand what is given with the other.[67]

Nicholls LJ in Johnston & Sons Ltd v Holland states that, ‘[a]s one would expect, the principle applies to all forms of grants.’[68] While English law does not recognise good faith as an implied obligation,[69] the Court of Appeal has recently applied the non-derogation from grant doctrine in the franchising context for the benefit of a franchisee. In Stone, the introduction of an e-commerce model impacted adversely on a franchisee’s business.[70] Although the franchisor was not prevented from implementing such a model by the franchise agreement (which did not contain provisions relating to internet sales),[71] the Court of Appeal held that this amounted to substantial impairment of the franchisee’s enjoyment of the rights acquired under the franchise agreement and thus amounted to a derogation from the grant:

The agreement, when read as a whole, cannot be construed as entitling the claimant [the franchisor] to impose such far-reaching restrictions on the franchisee’s ability to promote that part of the business where he [the franchisee] set the sale price directly with the customer.[72]

In Australia, the non-derogation from grant doctrine was recently considered in JLCS Pty Ltd v Squires Loft City Steakhouse Pty Ltd (‘Squires Loft’).[73] In that case, a restaurant licensee argued that an implied term existed in the licence which would provide a measure of protection of the goodwill generated from the use of a trademark in circumstances where the licensor proposed to license a restaurant operating under the same name within 500 metres.[74] Finkelstein J held that the principle of non-derogation from grant, while originally developed in relation to property and leasing cases, could be applied in a wider context,[75] which demonstrates increased recognition of the applicability of the concept to relational disputes. Finkelstein J inquired into the purpose of the grant of the licence and relied upon the fact that opening up another restaurant of similar name in close proximity to the existing one would ‘unduly interfere’ with the rights inherent in that grant by the licensor.[76] In a practical sense, this meant an obligation existed by which JLCS was ‘not to use, or permit the use of, the Squires Loft name in a location so proximate to the [licensee’s] city restaurant that it would likely result in a significant adverse effect on the goodwill’ of the licensee’s operation.[77]

The purpose of the doctrine is therefore to protect the spirit of the bargain struck. Based on current expectations of what a duty of good faith would achieve, the doctrine of non-derogation from grant could potentially cover the field and provide the knights of good faith with what they seek. The application of this doctrine in the franchise context in Stone and Squires Loft demonstrates that it may provide a better mechanism than an undefined, imprecise good faith obligation for dealing with a range of ‘good faith’ disputes in franchising, particularly in an encroachment context. However, due to the scarcity of case law, particularly superior court authority in Australia, the development of the non-derogation from grant doctrine in the franchise context is very much a work in progress.

C Unconscionability

In Shelanu Inc v Print Three Franchising Corporation, the Court of Appeal for Ontario quoted Paul Finn (now Finn J of the Federal Court of Australia):

‘Unconscionability’ accepts that one party is entitled as of course to act self-interestedly in his actions towards the other. Yet in deference to that other’s interests, it then proscribes excessively self-interested or exploitative conduct. ‘Good faith’, while permitting a party to act self-interestedly, nonetheless qualifies this by positively requiring that party, in his decision and action, to have regard to the legitimate interests therein of the other. The ‘fiduciary’ standard for its part enjoins one party to act in the interests of the other — to act selflessly and with undivided loyalty. There is, in other words, a progression from the first to the third: from selfish behaviour to selfless behaviour. Much the most contentious of the trio is the second, ‘good faith’. It often goes unacknowledged. It does embody characteristics to be found in the other two.[78]

While the above statement envisages a continuum, clear dividing lines between concepts along that continuum are seldom provided. In Renard Constructions (ME) Pty Ltd v Minister for Public Works (‘Renard’), Priestley JA stated that ‘there is a close association of ideas between the terms unreasonableness, lack of good faith, and unconscionability.’[79] While legislation in the form of s 51AC of the Trade Practices Act 1974 (Cth) (which prohibits unconscionable conduct in business transactions) is not limited to equitable principles of unconscientiously exploiting a special disadvantage,[80] the courts have come to different understandings of what constitutes ‘unconscionability’.[81] While the word itself connotes unscrupulous conduct which is undertaken without regard to conscience (for example, the franchisor’s actions in Australian Competition and Consumer Commission v Simply No-Knead (Franchising) Pty Ltd, where unconscionability was indicated by ‘an overwhelming case of unreasonable, unfair, bullying and thuggish behaviour’),[82] some courts have equated the concepts of unconscionability and good faith.[83]

The already unclear delineation between the concepts of unconscionability and good faith is further blurred by the ‘extent to which the supplier and the business consumer acted in good faith’ being one of the relevant factors a court may consider in its determination of whether conduct is unconscionable under s 51AC.[84] While this suggests a link between good faith and unconscionability, an absence of good faith is not determinative, but simply one of the twelve discretionary factors that do not define unconscionability but that may be taken into account in determining whether conduct was unconscionable.[85]

IV THE MEANING OF GOOD FAITH

The foregoing analysis of existing legal duties demonstrates that ‘[t]he mistrust of Anglo-Saxon jurists for the general concept of good faith is equalled only by the imagination which they put towards multiplying particular concepts which lead to the same results.’[86] The attempt to define what good faith actually encompasses must nevertheless be made, with the awareness that ‘general definitions of good faith either spiral into the Charybdis of vacuous generality or collide with the Scylla of restrictive specificity.’[87]

Good faith ‘has been described as a contextual standard’[88] and ‘a generalisation of universal application,’[89] with a standard of reasonableness having attracted the most support in recent Australian case law.[90] ‘The difficulty with [a] contextual standard or a “generalisation of universal application” … is [nevertheless] to identify the precise boundaries of this standard … [which] has evaded the grasp of precise judicial statement.’[91] Despite its long heritage in the US, the scope of the implied covenant of good faith remains elusive.

Uncertainty also reigns in Australia, with Peden commenting that ‘most judgments concerning the implication of good faith or cooperation terms appear incoherent and contain little legal principle.’[92]

In Council of the City of Sydney v Goldspar Australia Pty Ltd, Gyles J described the ‘variety of opinions’ in both the authorities and the commentaries as ‘bewildering’ and noted that approaches vary from the ‘cautious’ to the ‘adventurous’.[93] Jeannie Paterson argues that ‘Australian case law has relied on synonyms or isolated examples to explain the duty, an approach which leaves much unanswered.’[94] Such an approach impacts negatively on legal certainty and does not help in setting a standard for franchisees and franchisors to aspire to in their dealings.

A Good Faith as the Antithesis of Bad Faith The Excluder Approach

Lord Scott in Manifest Shipping Co Ltd v Uni-Polaris Shipping Co Ltd stated that ‘[u]nless the assured has acted in bad faith he cannot … be in breach of a duty of good faith, utmost or otherwise.’[95] Arguably, the simplest way to think of what a duty of good faith might require is to think of it as an obligation to eschew bad faith — the approach articulated by Associate Professor Summers over forty years ago.[96]

Summers sees good faith as a phrase which ‘is best understood as an “excluder” — it is a phrase which has no general meaning or meanings of its own, but which serves to exclude many heterogeneous forms of bad faith.’[97] His approach was characterised by the compilation of a list of bad faith behaviours, followed by a list of their opposites, in order to arrive at a more specific definition of good faith.[98] In Jobern Pty Ltd v BreakFree Resorts (Victoria) Pty Ltd, Gordon J provides an introduction to Summers’ excluder approach, taking guidance from previous cases in setting out what bad faith might encompass:

Specific conduct has also been identified by various courts as constituting ‘bad faith’ or a lack of ‘good faith’ including:

(1) acting arbitrarily, capriciously, unreasonably or recklessly …

(2) acting in a manner that is oppressive or unfair in its result by, for example, seeking to prevent the performance of the contract or to withhold its benefits …

(3) failing to have reasonable regards to the other party’s interests …

(4) failing to act ‘reasonably’ in general.[99]

Gordon J did not seem to place a great deal of emphasis on this characterisation of bad faith alone in the judgment.[100] Nevertheless, the repetition of the idea of reasonableness and related antonyms of arbitrariness, capriciousness, recklessness and unfairness (which themselves fail to paint a clear picture of what it is to act in bad faith), before ultimately washing out any meaning at all by impugning a failure to act reasonably in general, demonstrates a major weakness of the excluder approach: it does not provide enough guidance to courts or parties in determining whether conduct is or might be in breach of the implied obligation. In this way, the excluder approach fails to give a clear definition of what good or bad faith actually encompasses:

it seems tantamount to saying that the good faith duty is breached whenever a judge decides that it has been breached. This hardly advances the cause of intellectual inquiry and it provides absolutely no guide to the disposition of future cases, except to the extent that they may be on all fours with a decided case.[101]

While the idea of an excluder approach might appeal intuitively, it does not seem able of itself to guide either parties or courts in defining good faith behaviour with the degree of certainty required by contracting parties in commercial arrangements.[102]

B Good Faith as Honesty

In attempting to positively define good faith, perhaps the most uncontroversial proposition in this controversial debate is that good faith at least requires parties to act honestly, and therefore that acting dishonestly connotes bad faith conduct. The idea of good faith as requiring honest standards of dealing has made cameo appearances in some of the cases dealing with good faith in the franchise context.[103] While good faith may require honesty, this is not such a groundbreaking or instructive requirement for, as Einstein J states in Aiton Australia Pty Ltd v Transfield Pty Ltd, ‘parties are subject to a universal duty to act honestly’ in any case.[104] This supports the argument of Bergin J in Insight Oceania that the inclusion of a requirement to act honestly as part of a duty of good faith would be ‘otiose’.[105] The major problem with a standard of ‘honesty’ is not only the evidentiary challenge to a franchisee of proving dishonesty but also that it will not catch many forms of bad faith which are characterised by honest behaviour yet which nevertheless impact negatively and significantly upon the legitimate interests or expectations of the other.

C Good Faith as Fairness

If the idea of acting honestly adds little to a definition of good faith, recurring statements that good faith requires parties to act ‘fairly’ towards one another, ‘not only in relation to the performance of a contractual obligation, but also in the exercise of a power conferred by the contract’,[106] pose even greater challenges.

While an intuitively attractive idea, fairness is too abstract an ideal to which to subject contractual parties in the real world. This is probably why it has not received much support beyond its being tacked on to the end of sentences where good faith is mentioned in various judgments.[107] Indeed, the application of an abstract notion of fairness in the face of the exercise of hard, explicit contractual rights which might seem unfair in certain circumstances, yet which were in terms agreed to at formation with the intention of allowing parties to act in self-interested ways and to plan future action based on potential future options, poses obvious difficulties. What a franchisor may see as the fair exercise of contractual terms designed to protect its interests, a franchisee might perceive as completely unfair to the point of being unconscionable. Bingham LJ in Interfoto Picture Library Ltd v Stiletto Visual Programmes Ltd states that acting in good faith

does not simply mean that [parties] should not deceive each other … [I]ts effect is perhaps most aptly conveyed … as ‘playing fair’, ‘coming clean’ or ‘putting one’s cards face upwards on the table’. It is in essence a principle of fair and open dealing.[108]

While a higher standard of conduct might attend the successful execution of relational franchising contracts, defining this standard by reference to a concept such as fairness would fail to adequately provide guidance on what might be required of parties in any particular circumstance, largely because of the subjective nature of the concept. This would severely impact on the certainty necessary in dynamic business relationships where fortunes and futures hang in the balance. Indeed, it does not appear necessary to subject contractual parties to a standard so vague in their commercial dealings in order to achieve through good faith what its proponents would like it to do.

While the idea of fairness may go beyond a general duty of honesty in requiring the fair exercise of contractual terms, no guidance on what constitutes ‘fair’ has been given in the case law beyond not acting for ulterior motives or extraneous purposes. Professor Michael Bridge’s comment that good faith appears to be ‘a concept which means different things to different people in different moods at different times and in different places’[109]

is particularly compelling in relation to a concept of good faith based simply on fairness.

D Good Faith as the Absence of Opportunistic Conduct and Extraneous or Ulterior Purposes

A more specific formulation which involves application of the ideas of honesty and fairness in relation to the exercise of rights under contractual terms is the idea that good faith precludes contractual parties from acting opportunistically or using contractual terms for purposes antithetical to the contract that are calculated to extract value from the other contractual party. The problem with the use of contractual powers for reasons other than those envisioned at formation is that such behaviour would negatively impact on the certainty of the arrangement agreed upon and potentially affect the rights bargained for by the parties. This echoes the ‘foregone opportunities’ approach of Steven Burton,[110] whereby one party acts to reclaim opportunities surrendered at contract formation.[111] This was a feature of the Burger King litigation, where contractual powers to grant operational approval for new stores and to terminate the franchise agreement were used for purposes foreign to those envisioned at formation.[112] The actions were carried out in the context of Burger King’s ‘wishing to regain control of the Australian market’ and its ‘embark[ing] on a deliberate strategy to win back that market, which it acknowledged it had lost through its own neglect’, in pursuit of which it employed ‘a policy of confining, disrupting and thwarting the activities of [Hungry Jack’s] to the extent that it was within its interests to do so.’[113]

A clear explanation of what would constitute extraneous purposes or intentions in the franchise context is given by Dodds-Streeton J in Meridian Retail Pty Ltd v Australian Unity Retail Network Pty Ltd:

in my opinion an implied obligation of good faith would preclude the franchisor from exercising, or threatening to exercise, its literally unqualified power under the franchise agreement … in order to secure [the franchisees’] premature determination, negate their extended term and expropriate [their] interests at an undervalue.[114]

These concepts appear to aid in the analysis of conduct in cases involving a duty of good faith and may cover instances where contractual terms might have been abused as well as where contracts are silent on particular issues. They nevertheless closely resemble the doctrine of non-derogation from grant outlined above.[115] Actions motivated by ulterior purposes or by a desire to regain foregone opportunities may be regarded more helpfully as a derogation from the grant originally made.

E Good Faith as Legitimate Interests

In considering what good faith means in the franchise context, ‘it becomes necessary to enquire about the extent to which selflessness is required.’[116] According to most decisions, parties are not required to eschew their own self-interest or proprietary rights,[117] so long as the pursuit of any of these interests does not interfere with that party’s duty to cooperate to achieve the aims of the contract[118] and does not interfere ‘unreasonabl[y]’[119] with the enjoyment by the other party of benefits conferred by the contract (namely, in a way which renders them ‘nugatory, worthless or, perhaps, … seriously undermined’).[120] This does not equate to a fiduciary duty to prefer the other party’s interests to one’s own. The cases have insisted that good faith requires a party ‘to recognise and to have due regard to the legitimate interests of both the parties in the enjoyment of the fruits of the contract as delineated by its terms’, although the interests of the other party are not paramount.[121] If this be the case, what constitutes the legitimate interests to which parties are to have ‘due regard’? Could a legitimate interests approach work to allow the recognition of ‘interests’ not explicitly part of the written contract or to impose any restraint on the use of contractual powers which does not otherwise offend that contract? Another problem is that consideration of the other party’s interests has been explained as requiring ‘deal[ing] promptly, honestly, fairly and reasonably’ with that party[122] — concepts which are, in themselves, unclear.

The proposition that good faith ‘would not operate so as to restrict actions designed to promote the legitimate interests of [a] party’[123] is routinely expounded in the good faith case law and commentary. It gives rise to at least two distinct issues: whether ‘legitimate interests’ refers to strict contractual interests or wider commercial interests, and whether the standard would allow or deny a party the opportunity to pursue its own legitimate interests beyond a point where they result in the destruction or undermining of the other party’s business interests.

In Far Horizons Pty Ltd v McDonald’s Australia Ltd (‘Far Horizons’), Byrne J found that McDonald’s refusal to grant an existing franchisee the licence for new stores to be opened in the surrounding area was driven not by McDonald’s desire to punish the principal or the franchisee but by McDonald’s own legitimate interests.[124] McDonald’s could demonstrate commercial reasons for its conduct in choosing to offer new stores to new franchisees and thus was held not to have made the decisions in bad faith.[125] Byrne J nevertheless acknowledged that there may be limits on the extent to which franchisors can adversely affect a franchisee’s business and left ‘for another day’ extreme cases where the franchisor acted so as to ‘effectively destroy’ the business for which the franchisee had bargained.[126]

Far Horizons can be contrasted with the decision in Laurelmont Pty Ltd v Stockdale & Leggo (Queensland) Pty Ltd, where Dutney J agreed with the trial judge that there was a distinction between the conscious yet incidental, as opposed to the willingly intentional, destruction of a franchisee’s business.[127] With regard to the former situation, it was not thought necessary to imply a term to restrain the franchisor from acting in a way that had this result, while in the latter situation a court may imply such a term:

If the [franchisor’s] commercial interest would be benefited by a dealing which incidentally may have the effect of damaging or destroying the business of a franchisee, I do not think it is necessary to give business efficacy to the franchise agreement to imply a term preventing the franchisor from so conducting itself. That is different from the implication of a term that the first defendant or second defendant not conduct itself with the object of damaging or destroying the business of the [franchisee’s] Maroochydore office. Such a term may be necessary to give business efficacy to a franchise agreement.[128]

Dutney J seems to accord little weight to the fact that he was dealing with a franchised business and that both parties’ interests were held within each other’s control; each party might therefore expect that they would consider the other’s interests and possibly avoid harming them rather than engaging in conduct which would be damaging to the business. On the other hand, Dutney J is probably just stating the tougher side of the usual rhetoric that parties to a franchise contract need only have ‘due regard’ for the other party’s legitimate interests without needing to sacrifice their own. As soon as one party can say, ‘I have considered your legitimate interests, yet I choose to engage in a particular course of conduct detrimental to them, which I have a right to do as per this contract’, good faith appears paralysed and thus unable to effect the levelling of the field of economic action on which franchise agreements operate.

The Court in Burger King (Appeal) also took this approach, stating that a requirement that powers be exercised in good faith would not restrain Burger King from pursuing its own legitimate interests, so long as it did not do so for a purpose extraneous to the contract.[129] This idea is expressed more precisely, and without the baggage of extraneous purposes, in Overlook by Barrett J in the proposition that good faith does not require subordination of one’s own interests

so long as pursuit of those interests does not entail unreasonable interference with the enjoyment of a benefit conferred by the express contractual terms so that the enjoyment becomes (or could become) … ‘nugatory, worthless or, perhaps, [be] seriously undermined’.[130]

On Barrett J’s analysis, the sources to be looked to in order to determine whether unreasonable interference has occurred are the ‘express contractual terms’ and the benefits conferred by them. The problem is that relational contracts, of which franchising contracts are a species, are necessarily incomplete and beset by the realities of standard form contracts and power imbalance. If the legitimate interests approach is set to work solely on contractual terms, ‘courts [would] fail to protect fully one half of the interests necessary to support the franchise relationship.’[131]

While Barrett J does look at the overall character of the agreement, in order to gain an ‘appreciation of the prohibitory or negative spirit with which the contracts are infused’[132] and therefore protect expectations of enjoyment of the contractual terms from being undermined, this approach demonstrates the reality of Hadfield’s criticism: that legitimate interests is too high a threshold for the effective operation of good faith in order to protect both parties to the franchise contract.[133]

This problem is also mirrored in the guidance that good faith may preclude actions that would render rights nugatory, worthless, or seriously undermined — there remains a wide margin for error on the part of the franchisor before any actions have this effect.[134]

Indeed, how prohibitory could the character of a standard form contract weighted in the franchisor’s interest possibly be on actions engaged in by the stronger party? Standard form contracts are designed to afford maximum freedom to the franchisor, meaning that there is not much for good faith to operate on for the benefit of a franchisee if the approach to legitimate interests outlined above is taken. This approach would set too high a threshold for franchisees to benefit from the operation of a good faith requirement. It would allow any rational business decision made in the franchisor’s interests to trump the idea of good faith as existing to level the playing field on which the relationship takes shape. It would lead to conclusions such as that of Barrett J in Overlook, describing a business decision as, ‘on its face, … quite a reasonable commercial proposition, at least in abstract terms’[135] — a conclusion which in effect could be drawn of nearly any business conduct unless it had no reason whatsoever and was truly arbitrary.

As such, a legitimate interests approach centred on express contractual terms appears to protect the rights of the franchisor, yet would do little to protect the investment and interests of franchisees who enter a standard form contract with only the expectation (for the contract itself rarely would make requirements, in words, of the franchisor) that the franchisor remain accountable to the relationship supposedly created for their mutual benefit. This approach seems to land us back at the beginning — parties must cooperate to fulfil contractual ends. It is difficult to see what an implied term of good faith adds if independent duties of cooperation and non-derogation from grant cover the same ground.

This illustrates the fact that all the franchisee really has to hold onto in the absence of express contractual terms in a relational standard form contract is the expectations created by the franchisor, and the relationship as such, as opposed to the franchisor’s ‘hard’ business interests specified in the contract. The business interests approach assists the franchisor by focusing on contractually expressed interests rather than helping remedy the situation that allows for a standard form contract heavily weighted against the franchisee to represent the entirety of the relationship. Framed in this way, a requirement of good faith might find it difficult to level the playing field such that both parties’ continuing interests in the relationship can be recognised, not solely the franchisor’s business imperatives. This would amount to treating the franchisee as the franchisor’s risk-taker, a position no rational person would accept without adequate return on their investment for their risk.

This is why, as Hadfield argues, there should be due consideration not only for the state of affairs apparent when the franchisee entered the contract but also for the continuing relationship and the expectations engendered therein.[136]

This suggests another approach to good faith, which is to consider the ‘reasonable expectations’ of parties to a contract.

F Good Faith as Regard for Reasonable Expectations

The limitations on the scope of the legitimate interests test outlined above in achieving what is desired in a standard of good faith may be ameliorated with support from a test of reasonable expectations. As noted by Summers, ‘[i]n most cases the party acting in bad faith frustrates the justified expectations of another … [and] the ways in which he may do this are numerous and radically diverse.’[137]

Possibly for the latter reason, the reasonable expectations approach has received little judicial attention, although it appears to underlie the approaches outlined above. The reasonable expectations approach was referred to by Barrett J in Overlook when his Honour outlined the process of maintaining the integrity of a contract in these circumstances. Achieving this would require

an appreciation of the prohibitory or negative spirit with which the contracts are infused in order to protect the parties’ legitimate expectations of enjoyment from being rendered nugatory or worthless or seriously undermined … [T]he court must proceed to decide whether the conduct of Foxtel was, in the light of [these matters], such as to cause those legitimate expectations of enjoyment to be affected in any of the ways mentioned.[138]

Under a reasonable expectations approach — which is arguably wider than the legitimate interests approach — courts may be able to take a more balanced approach to franchising disputes by allowing to franchisees, who might have had their legitimate expectations of contractual performance frustrated and are not able to make a case in situations where they do not possess formal ‘legitimate interests’ (as specified in a written contract), a valid avenue for redress they otherwise would not have had.

The application of a reasonable expectations test might require a court to take account of business norms structuring the relationship. Sir Anthony Mason has commented that:

The implied obligation does no more than spell out what, on the true construction of the contract, is the effect of promises and undertakings entered into by the party. In reaching that construction, it will be relevant to take account of the legitimate or reasonable expectations of the parties when they make the contract.[139]

Such a formulation supports a consideration of the expectations of each party at the time of formation and entry into a contract, but it mentions nothing of the idea that expectations can change and original contractual terms can be overlapping and thus be superseded by new norms and expectations. An example of their having done so comes from the Burger King litigation, where both parties were engaged in tripartite negotiations with Shell to begin operations at Shell service stations.[140] With the intention to proceed on a test site basis, ‘there was a clear expectation by the parties that the test site arrangements were being pursued in the context of a potentially longer term relationship in which, at the least, the parties would be joint venturers.’[141] Hungry Jack’s legitimate expectations led it to act in ways it otherwise would not have done and thus to suffer loss when Burger King frustrated these expectations.

An important consideration in the use of the reasonable expectations approach, as noted by Joel Iglesias, is that ‘what a party can reasonably expect must be determined not on subjective hopes, but on economic reality.’[142] A reasonable expectations approach seems to be broad enough to include reference to norms of the relationship as designated by the contract and the understanding surrounding it — arguably the very point of good faith being applied in franchise cases. This seems to be a barely disguised consideration in various cases where courts seem to be embracing a ‘relational approach albeit not in the language of it.’[143]

If good faith were restricted to working on express contractual terms, as in the approach in Overlook described above, the norms underlying the relationship would be defeated by express terms every time, allowing a franchisor to do as it wished regardless of a franchisee’s reasonable expectations. It appears that the knights of good faith wish the concept to have the ability to question whether the franchisor has considered the rights and legitimate expectations of franchisees and the franchise relationship in its decision-making.

At the very least, good faith as reasonable expectations would need to be able to work on the underlying understanding between the parties at formation and should be open to evidence other than the bare face of the contract. The franchisor’s sales pitch and promotional material may thus constitute evidence of a reasonable expectation in the circumstances (in the absence of conflicting contractual terms) and may serve to assist the court in getting into the frame of mind of a franchisee who was contemplating the acquisition of a franchise, in analysing what legitimate expectations a franchisee would have in the circumstances and whether these interests had been given due regard. Such an approach would overcome any difficulties with the legitimate interests approach as applied by Barrett J.

While it may appear to be broad-brush, the reasonable expectations approach might just fit the necessary requirements for a standard of good faith, with Bridge going so far as to state that

[t]his reference to justified expectations … is much more satisfactory than good faith as a guide to the resolution of practical problems. It is particularly apt in explaining a number of the movements that have taken place in recent years in a dynamic Anglo-Canadian law of contract.[144]

It should be said, however, that the idea of reasonable expectations bears an uncanny resemblance to the established doctrine of non-derogation from grant and the reasonable expectations one party might hold in relation to a particular grant.

G Good Faith as Community Standards

Generally considered to be the initial foray into the ‘community standards’ wilderness were Priestley JA’s comments in Renard:

As the words used in the sequence of statutes show, the ideas of unconscionability, unfairness, and lack of good faith have a great deal in common. The result is that people generally, including judges and other lawyers, from all strands of the community, have grown used to the courts applying standards of fairness to contract which are wholly consistent with the existence in all contracts of a duty upon the parties of good faith and fair dealing in its performance. In my view this is in these days the expected standard, and anything less is contrary to prevailing community expectations.[145]

Priestley JA expressly excluded these comments from his ratio decidendi in that case;[146] they thus formed obiter statements on good faith generally. To say, however, that Priestley JA ‘adopted … an approach’ ‘whereby the measure of good faith performance is based on standards imposed by a “judging community” independent of the contractual parties’[147]

is incorrect. On a careful reading, Priestley JA is not saying that community standards constitute or even inform the test for good faith. He merely says that enforcing good faith (whatever the meaning attached to it by the court) reflects community standards and expectations for the resolution of matters by the courts. Indeed, no subsequent case has attempted to apply this vague idea. As noted by Bill Dixon:

In the same manner that Finn J has expressly disavowed the invocation of ‘community standards’ in the good faith debate, perhaps his judicial brethren have also recognised the perilous nature of this territory and have preferred to base their judicial responses on the far less contentious, and longstanding, basis of reasonable expectations.[148]

H Good Faith as Reasonableness

Over a century ago, Bowen LJ commented on the concept of reasonable standards for commercial contracting in The Mogul Steamship Co Ltd v McGregor, Gow & Co:

I myself should deem it to be a misfortune if we were to attempt to … adopt some standard of judicial ‘reasonableness’ … to which commercial adven-turers, otherwise innocent, were bound to conform.[149]

Despite a renaissance in some cases, the caution of Bowen LJ retains much of its force. In Garry Rogers — a case involving the use of a termination clause by a franchisor — Finkelstein J stated that, ‘provided the party exercising the power acts reasonably in all the circumstances, the duty to act fairly and in good faith will ordinarily be satisfied.’[150] Although this might be overstating the content of a good faith obligation operative in business relationships, this has provided a platform for exploration of the content of such an obligation in subsequent cases.

In Far Horizons, Byrne J felt bound by the authorities following Renard and stated that a ‘good faith’ obligation would oblige ‘each party to exercise the powers conferred upon it by the agreement in good faith and reasonably, and not capriciously or for some extraneous purpose.’[151] Reasonable exercise of contractual powers would thus preclude impulsive actions which lack a rational basis altogether, as well as those which may be all ‘too rational’ to the extent they were calculated to extract a benefit extraneous to the contract between the parties. The equating of good faith with reasonableness has, not surprisingly, been criticised as being ‘more confusing than instructive.’[152]

As Peden has observed:

There is no precise meaning given, but rather a repetition of well-worn phrases and quotes, without explanation of how and why they fit together. There is, furthermore, no explanation of why ‘reasonableness’ is a justified inclusion in the meaning of good faith, and why it is considered identical to ‘good faith’.[153]

This can be said of most cases in which a consideration of ‘reasonableness’ appears. A further problem could be that which Priestley JA discussed in Renard regarding the commonality of meanings between the terms ‘good faith’ and ‘reasonableness’:

in ordinary English usage there has been constant association between the words fair and reasonable. Similarly, there is a close association of ideas between the terms unreasonableness, lack of good faith, and unconscionability.[154]

While the NSW Court of Appeal in Burger King (Appeal) also emphasised that ‘the Australian cases make no distinction of substance between the implied term of reasonableness and that of good faith’,[155] neither the Court of Appeal nor subsequent decisions have developed the case for good faith as reasonableness. While there may be an overlap in their content, it has been argued that ‘[t]he interrelationship of and difference between good faith and reasonableness is subtle but of great importance. A requirement to satisfy a standard of reasonable behaviour is more demanding than the requirement of good faith.’[156] Indeed, notwithstanding these linguistic issues, to require parties to a commercial contract to temper their conduct by reference to ‘reasonable’ standards of conduct has implications for the fundamental need for certainty in franchise contracting, despite its relational nature.

The principle recently referred to by Kirby J in Koompahtoo Local Aboriginal Land Council v Sanpine Pty Ltd (‘Sanpine’) — ‘that parties should ordinarily fulfil their contractual obligations’[157] — is of course not sacrosanct, as common law and legislative developments in relation to standards of behaviour in commercial contracting demonstrate. A further encroachment on this principle by way of a bare standard of ‘reasonableness’ is unlikely to attract as much support as one based on ‘reasonable commercial standards’. The latter approach has been taken in Canada in the four provinces which have enacted franchise-specific laws. Each impose on both franchisor and franchisee ‘a duty of fair dealing in the performance and enforcement of the franchise agreement.’[158] In Ontario, Prince Edward Island and New Brunswick — and under the Uniform Franchises Act (a model law prepared by the Uniform Law Conference of Canada in 2005)[159] — the duty of ‘fair dealing’ includes ‘the duty to act in good faith and in accordance with reasonable commercial standards’.[160] In 1323257 Ontario Ltd v Hyundai Auto Canada Corp, the Ontario Superior Court of Justice considered, in interlocutory proceedings, an express good faith clause in the National Automobile Dealer Arbitration Program (‘NADAP’) Rules for Dispute Resolution.[161] This clause, which required parties to a dealer agreement to interpret, apply, perform and enforce agreements, and exercise unilateral or discretionary rights in good faith, was defined as follows:

‘Good Faith’ — means the observance of reasonable commercial standards by balancing, where, and to the extent relevant, the interests of the Manufacturer, the Dealer, the collective interests of the Manufacturer and all of its dealers, and the interest of the customers of all of its dealers, and by recognizing the competitive nature of the automotive industry.[162]

The Court held, with little discussion, that the franchisor’s non-disclosure of material facts gave rise to a serious question to be tried.[163] A starting point for consideration of a definition of good faith based on reasonable commercial standards may be the NADAP definition, with the references to ‘manufacturer’ and ‘dealer’ replaced by ‘franchisor’ and ‘franchisee’, and the reference to the ‘automotive industry’ replaced by reference to ‘the industry sector in which the franchise operates’.

V LIMITATIONS ON A GOOD FAITH OBLIGATION

Apart from limitations inherent in the as yet undefined scope of the implied term, there exist three potential limitations on the capacity of a good faith obligation to operate, as some argue it should, as a broad mechanism for promoting ethical conduct in business:

• Can good faith impose obligations inconsistent with other terms of the agreement?

• Can good faith be excluded?

• Can good faith be an independent source of obligations or must it relate to a violation in bad faith of an express term of the agreement?

These will now be examined in turn.

A Good Faith and Inconsistent Contractual Provisions

The Australian and US authorities overwhelmingly support the proposition that any implied term of good faith must be consistent with the explicit terms of the contract. The proposition of Justice Robert McDougall, writing extra-judicially, that the courts cannot imply a duty of good faith ‘inconsistently with the express language of the contract, or necessary implications therefrom’[164]

has wide support. In Ingot Capital Investments Pty Ltd v Macquarie Equity Capital Markets Ltd [No 6] (‘Ingot Capital Investments [No 6]’), McDougall J stated:

it is plain that no duty of good faith can be implied where the duty … is inconsistent with an express term of the contract … Further, even if there is no direct conflict between the term sought to be implied and any express term of the contract, the express terms of the contract as a whole may negate the implication …[165]

In Insight Oceania, Bergin J expressed this clearly: she stated that the duty ‘does not rise above the promises made by the parties to the contract’[166] and, quoting Alcatel Australia Ltd v Scarcella, that it ‘cannot over-ride the express provisions of the contract’.[167]

While the determination of whether there is, in Bergin J’s words, an express contractual term which will trump the implied obligations may be relatively straightforward, the exercise becomes much more complex if good faith can be excluded by necessary implication. This was suggested by Greenwood J in Luce Optical Pty Ltd v Budget Specs (Franchising) Pty Ltd:

good faith is an incident of every commercial contract unless the duty is excluded expressly or by necessary implication and … the duty operates as a fetter upon the exercise of discretions and powers conferred by the contract …[168]

B Excluding Good Faith

It follows from the above that the implied obligation of good faith can be excluded by an appropriate exclusion clause — the ‘express contractual provision will trump an implied contractual provision.’[169]

Whether ‘entire agreement’ clauses have the effect of excluding the implied obligation of good faith is less certain.[170]

In Ingot Capital Investments [No 6], McDougall J left open the question as to whether the express terms of the contract as a whole may negate the implication of a duty of good faith.[171] In NT Power Generation Pty Ltd v Power and Water Authority, Mansfield J in the Federal Court held that an appropriately drafted entire agreement clause would be construed as inconsistent with and would therefore exclude the implication of terms into an agreement,[172] including an implied condition of good faith.[173] However, doubt as to this view was expressed by Finn J in GEC Marconi Systems Pty Ltd v BHP Information Technology Pty Ltd, referring to a difficulty of ‘distinctly doctrinal character’:

Is the duty one that can be excluded by agreement? On one view, reflected in civilian legal systems and § 1-102(3) of the Uniform Commercial Code, the very rationale of the duty in contract law precludes its exclusion. But as a matter of legal doctrine in this country it must be accepted that, as an implied term, it is capable of being excluded by express or by inconsistent provision — although it is, perhaps, difficult to envisage an express provision authorising dishonesty.[174]

His Honour considered that, under Australian law, an entire agreement clause does not preclude implications ad hoc and found ‘arresting the suggestion that an entire agreement clause is of itself sufficient to constitute an “express exclusion” of an implied duty of good faith and fair dealing where that implication would otherwise have been made by law.’[175]

If in accordance with the recommendation of the Opportunity Not Opportunism Report a good faith obligation is added to the Code, the issue of express exclusion will not arise. An obligation to act in good faith will then be a legislative, public duty that cannot be excluded, contracted out of or waived. The question of the role for good faith in the face of inconsistent contractual provisions will nevertheless remain an important issue to be worked through.

C Good Faith as an Independent Source of Obligations

The standard expression of the good faith obligation is that it is implied in relation to the exercise of contractual powers. The issue of whether an obligation of good faith can arise independently of contractual terms has not been authoritatively resolved. Peden suggests that ‘[i]n Australia there is reluctance to require an obligation of good faith or cooperation that is independent of express terms of the contract’[176] and that ‘[i]t has been said that to state there is a term requiring good faith without some obligation on which to attach it would be to place the obligation in a “vacuum”.’[177]

Cases such as Far Horizons nevertheless suggest that the judicial reluctance may be less compelling in the franchising context. In that case, Byrne J rejected the plaintiff’s claims that the decision of McDonald’s to open two new stores in the vicinity of those already operated by the franchisee was actuated not by legitimate commercial considerations but by a desire to punish the plaintiff franchisee and pressure it to leave or to make an example of it (to warn potentially dissident licensees).[178]

The franchisee had rights only to one site, with no territorial exclusivity or contractual right to a further outlet, but McDonald’s had not expressly stipulated in the contract that they had the right to open other outlets in the vicinity of the franchisee’s outlet.[179] Byrne J commented that:

In the present case, two parties to a contract have interests which are in conflict in the circumstances which have arisen. One party wishes to perform an act which the law ordinarily would permit it to do — to open a new store. This may have an adverse effect upon the other party. The right to perform that act is not conferred by the contract but by the ordinary freedom of a commercial enterprise to pursue a commercial opportunity. The act is not, in terms, prohibited by the contract. The question is not, as in Renard …, whether the right conferred by the contract is fettered by the terms of the contract; rather it is whether the contract between the parties impliedly prohibits or limits the right of one of them to perform an otherwise lawful act. In such a case the contract will operate to prohibit or limit the performance of that act by a party to a contract only where this prohibition or limitation is necessary for the performance by that party of its obligations under the contract.[180]

Byrne J concluded that McDonald’s exercise of its right to open a competing store that would have an impact on an existing franchisee was not subject to alleged implied restrictions, at least in circumstances where the franchisee had no exclusive territorial rights.[181] His Honour nevertheless stated:

I leave for another day the case where the impact caused by the new store is such that it effectively destroys the business which the impacted operator had bargained for or where the degree of impact is such as to give rise to the inference that its opening was for a purpose which might give rise to the operation of the implied obligation of good faith and fair dealing.[182]

In Overlook, the essential question was

whether the relevant implied obligation of good faith inhibits one party in the performance of ‘an act which the law [ordinarily would] permit it to do’ in exercise of ‘the ordinary freedom of a commercial enterprise to pursue a commercial opportunity’ …[183]

Barrett J accepted that there was scope for the operation of an implied obligation of good faith in circumstances which did not involve the exercise of a contractual power or performance of a contractual obligation:

the conduct of Foxtel in reducing the price of the add-on channels falls to be assessed in a context where there was no express or implied contractual provision precluding or regulating alteration of the price by Foxtel and where Foxtel’s actions were not taken pursuant to or in purported exercise or fulfilment of any contractual provision.[184]

In cases such as Far Horizons and Overlook, the good faith issue was not tied to contractual provisions. Indeed, the influence of good faith would be greatly reduced if this limitation were absolute.

VI ENACTING A GOOD FAITH OBLIGATION FOR FRANCHISING

In recommending that the Code be amended by including a provision imposing a duty on franchisors and franchisees to ‘act in good faith’ in relation to all aspects of a franchisee agreement, the Opportunity Not Opportunism Report quoted the South Australian Report:

While an abstract formulation of a generalised concept of good faith may be indistinct, the courts have demonstrated that they are able to know it when they see it, or more properly, they know a breach of it when they see it.[185]

The ‘know it when you see it’ test was of course made famous by Stewart J in Jacobellis v Ohio in relation to pornography, his Honour commenting: ‘I shall not today attempt further to define the kinds of material I understand to be embraced within that shorthand description … But I know it when I see it’.[186]

The reality is that good faith — like pornography and unconscionability — is, in the absence of clear definition, in the eye of the beholder. Unless there is a clear consensus as to the scope and operation of good faith — which, given Australia’s ‘bewildering’ array of authorities,[187] there is clearly not — the ‘know it when you see it’ approach is an abdication of legislative responsibility. Even if the judges know it when they see it, the evidence from the Australian courts is that they know this individually and not collectively. In any event, the law is not for the judges but for the community and the prescience of various judges is not necessarily mirrored in the franchising community.

A legislative obligation of good faith in the Code would undoubtedly have the capacity for a more liberal interpretation and more influential development than its common law progenitor.[188]

It would be freed from the common law restraint noted by Kirby J in the High Court in Royal Botanic Gardens — that it ‘appears to conflict with fundamental notions of caveat emptor that are inherent (statute and equitable intervention apart) in common law conceptions of economic freedom.’[189] It would be interpreted against the background of extrinsic material which clearly addresses the ‘mischief’ the amendment would seek to remedy.[190] It could not be excluded by the convenient expedient of an appropriate exclusion clause. It would nevertheless be, at least as currently envisaged, a legislative obligation which encompasses the common law principle. The lessons from the unconscionability regime are instructive. A decade after the introduction of the business unconscionability provision in s 51AC of the Trade Practices Act 1974 (Cth),[191] the interpretation of the core concept — ‘unconscionability’ — remains unsettled.[192]

A broad and general entrenchment of the ethical command ‘good faith’ raises even more complex and sensitive issues.

One alternative suggested to the Joint Committee was to define ‘good faith’.[193]

Given the magnitude of this task it is hardly surprising that the Joint Committee declined the invitation. The Australian Competition and Consumer Commission (‘ACCC’) was certainly not exaggerating in suggesting that it would be difficult to independently define good faith or reduce it to a ‘rigid rule’.[194] A more satisfactory alternative is to address specific sector problems by specific legislative solutions.

VII CONCLUSION

Kirby J in Sanpine recently observed that:

Because the common law develops from hundreds of judicial decisions, sometimes over long periods of time, it is often the case that the conceptual framework that affords structure to a group of related legal principles is at first imperfect and unclear. It falls to judges and scholars to attempt to derive rules that are coherent, practical, just, and (so far as is possible) conformable with past decisions.[195]

Kirby J was writing in the context of the principle that parties should ordinarily fulfil their contractual obligations, but his observation is equally applicable to the current development of the principle of good faith. Commenting specifically on judicial recognition of good faith in Esso Australia, Warren CJ referred to ‘the conceptual difficulty that can attend the concept of a duty of good faith’,[196] which has frequently been avoided by the courts deciding matters on other bases:

The difficulty is that the standard is nebulous. Therefore, the current reticence attending the application and recognition of a duty of good faith probably lies as much with the vagueness and imprecision inherent in defining commercial morality. The modern law of contract has developed on the premise of achieving certainty in commerce. If good faith is not readily capable of definition then that certainty is undermined.[197]

In contrast, the Opportunity Not Opportunism Report argued that the introduction of an express obligation of good faith will ‘provide a clear, overreaching statement of expectation as to the standard of conduct that should be adopted by franchisors, franchisees and prospective franchisees.’[198]

As magnificent as this sentiment undoubtedly is, it has the potential to propel the franchising sector into a new era of uncertainty, disputation and litigation, with notions of good faith being sought to be applied to an indeterminate range of real and imagined grievances and breaches. The Joint Committee acknowledged but was unmoved by the submission of the ACCC (that a good faith obligation ‘may introduce ambiguity and confusion about the rights and responsibilities of franchisors and franchisees, and potentially increase disputes and conflict among franchising participants’)[199] and the evidence of its Chairman, Mr Graeme Samuel, who was concerned that an explicit good faith clause in the Code may add to the expectation gap in franchise relationships:

On top of the prescriptive requirements of the Franchising Code of Conduct and of the relatively low threshold of misleading and deceptive conduct, that is, have you been honest or have you been dishonest, layer on top of that this somewhat hazy, woolly concept of good faith, and all I can say to you is that we will end up having an increased expectation gap where people will say, ‘But I believe that the franchisor did not act in good faith, and the ACCC wouldn’t deal with it.’[200]

The assumption of the South Australian Report — that, ‘[w]hile an abstract formulation of a generalised concept of good faith may be indistinct, the courts have demonstrated that they are able to know it when they see it, or more properly, they know a breach of it when they see it’[201]

— is misconceived or, at least, too optimistic. The report’s endorsement of the proposition that ‘a statutory duty of good faith would be one way to make explicit the underlying ethical standards expected of the industry as a whole’[202]

is naive and troubling. The statement of the Opportunity Not Opportunism Report that despite no clear definition of good faith this concept ‘would be generally understood to mean acting fairly, reasonably and honestly, encapsulating the concept of “a fair go”’[203]

is concerning.

The concept of good faith has gained traction as the solution to all real and imagined ills within the franchising sector. For those agitating for reform it has assumed symbolic significance and, if introduced, would be argued to accommodate circumstances beyond any appropriate sphere of influence. ‘Good faith’ is a seductive concept for franchisees and for the franchise regulators, but it will not be interpreted by the courts to provide the universal solvent the knights of good faith seek. The Aussie mantra of ‘a fair go’ is a beautiful thing but the operation of good faith will be interpreted much more narrowly. The perception that ‘good faith’ is the universal solution is both misleading and dangerous, but is given life by the equating of good faith with good ethics. A principle of good faith must presumably accord with ethical standards and community values, but is not, and should not be, a concept the content of which is defined by them.

While an understanding of good faith as requiring ‘a fair go’ would be enthusiastically perceived as a panacea for both the real and imagined ills of the sector, the reality of good faith as a legal concept is quite different. If franchisor opportunism is a problem warranting legislative intervention, this should be addressed by carefully crafted legislative responses rather than by defaulting to an undefined and overreaching standard of indeterminate scope and application.

VIII POSTSCRIPT

On 5 November 2009, the Commonwealth government released its response to the Opportunity Not Opportunism Report.[204] The government rejected the Joint Committee’s recommendation for the introduction of an overarching standard of good faith to be incorporated into the Code:

While accepting the intent of Recommendation 8, there are some difficulties with the suggested approach. The law on good faith is still evolving and there is not a single definition or standard set of behaviours that constitute good faith. The inclusion of a general obligation of good faith in the Franchising Code would increase uncertainty in franchising. Neither franchisors nor franchisees would be certain of the occurrence of a breach: court proceedings would be required to establish whether or not there had been a breach.
The extra uncertainty created by the inclusion in the Franchising Code of a general, undefined good-faith obligation could be expected to have adverse commercial consequences for franchisees.[205]

The government’s approach is that specific issues ‘should be dealt with by measures which will address specific behavioural concerns.’[206]

The government regarded this response as one that is ‘legally feasible and avoids undesirable commercial consequences for franchising’ as well as ‘avoid[ing] unnecessary uncertainty and associated extra costs for franchisees and franchisors.’[207]


[*] LLB (Hons), LLM (Hons) (Cant); Professor and Head, School of Business Law and Taxation, Australian School of Business, The University of New South Wales.

[†] BCom, LLB (Hons), BA (Hons) (Macq); Associate Lecturer, Discipline of Business Law, The University of Sydney.

[1] Franchising is a significant business relationship in Australia, with a sales turnover in 2007 estimated at $130 billion: Lorelle Frazer, Scott Weaven and Owen Wright, Asia-Pacific Centre for Franchising Excellence, Franchising Australia 2008 Survey (2008) 10 <http://www.griffith.edu.au/__data/assets/pdf_file/0008/101051/fa2008-web-version.pdf> . The Franchising Australia 2008 Survey found 1100 business-format franchise systems operating in Australia in 2008 (a growth rate of 14.6 per cent from the previous survey in 2006) and a total of 71 400 business units (63 500 franchised and 7900 company owned — a growth rate of 15.4 per cent from 2006): at 9–10. The survey also found that 413 000 people were employed in business-format franchise systems in 2008: at 10.

[2] See generally Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Parliament of Australia, Opportunity Not Opportunism: Improving Conduct in Australian Franchising (2008) (‘Opportunity Not Opportunism Report’). Chapter 8 of the report noted numerous submissions supporting (and opposing) the case for the incorporation of a standard of good faith in the Franchising Code of Conduct.

[3] Trade Practices (Industry Code Franchising) Regulations 1998 (Cth) sch (‘Franchising Code of Conduct’).

[4] Trade Practices (Industry Code Franchising) Regulations 1998 (Cth) reg 3.

[5] See E Allan Farnsworth, ‘Good Faith Performance and Commercial Reasonableness under the Uniform Commercial Code(1963) 30 University of Chicago Law Review 666, 669–70, who outlines the classical origins of the ‘venerable shibboleth’ of good faith in Roman law and its passage into the English common law.

[6] Bill Dixon, ‘Can the Common Law Obligation of Good Faith Be Contractually Excluded?’ (2007) 35 Australian Business Law Review 110, 110.

[7] Hunter Valley Skydiving Centre Pty Ltd v Central Coast Aero Club Ltd [2008] NSWSC 539 (Unreported, Brereton J, 3 June 2008) [48].

[8] Uniform Commercial Code § 1-304 (2004).

[9] See, eg, Zapatha v Dairy Mart Inc, 381 Mass 284, 289 fn 7, 291 (Wilkins J for Hennessey CJ, Quirico, Braucher, Wilkins and Abrams JJ) (1980).

[10] Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 205 (1981) states that ‘[e]very contract imposes upon each party a duty of good faith and fair dealing in its performance and its enforcement.’

[11] Thomas M Pitegoff and W Michael Garner, ‘Franchise Relationship Laws’ in Rupert M Barkoff and Andrew C Seldon (eds), Fundamentals of Franchising (3rd ed, 2008) 183, 224 (citations omitted).

[12] See Jani-King (GB) Ltd v Pula Enterprises Ltd [2007] EWCA Civ 620; [2008] 1 All ER (Comm) 451, 466–7 (Judge Coulson).

[13] [2006] EWCA Civ 1209 (Unreported, Keene, Wall and Wilson LJJ, 31 August 2006).

[14] See, eg, Shelanu Inc v Print Three Franchising Corporation (2003) 64 OR (3d) 533, 540 (Weiler JA for Weiler, Austin and Laskin JJA) (Ontario Court of Appeal) (‘Shelanu’). See also Shannon Kathleen O’Byrne, ‘The Implied Term of Good Faith and Fair Dealing: Recent Developments’ (2007) 86 Canadian Bar Review 193, 218.

[15] Franchises Act, RSA 2000, c F-23, s 7 (Alberta); Franchises Act, SNB 2007, c F-23.5, ss 3(1), (3) (New Brunswick); Arthur Wishart Act (Franchise Disclosure), SO 2000, c 3, ss 3(1), (3) (Ontario); Franchises Act, RSPEI 1988, c F-14.1, ss 3(1), (3) (Prince Edward Island).

[16] See Franchising Code Review Committee, Review of the Disclosure Provisions of the Franchising Code of Conduct Report to the Hon Fran Bailey MP (2006) (‘Matthews Report’); Government of Western Australia, Inquiry into the Operation of Franchise Businesses in Western AustraliaReport to the Western Australian Minister for Small Business (2008); Economic and Finance Committee, Parliament of South Australia, Final Report Franchises, Report No 65 (2008) (‘South Australian Report’); Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2.

[17] Matthews Report, above n 16, 47.

[18] Ibid (recommendation 25).

[19] Australian Government, Response to the Review of the Disclosure Provisions of the Franchising Code of Conduct (2007) 9 <http://www.innovation.gov.au/Section/SmallBusiness/Pages/FranchisingCodeofConduct.aspx> .

[20] South Australian Report, above n 16, 59.

[21] Ibid 60, 98.

[22] The Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, is the most comprehensive report — a 125-page report containing 11 significant recommendations. The Joint Committee received approximately 170 submissions, held public hearings across the country and heard from over 50 witnesses: see at 127–35. It also had the benefit of the accumulated wisdom, or otherwise, of the earlier reports. And the federal report was always going to be the most influential given that the Code is a federal responsibility.

[23] Ibid 101 (citations omitted).

[24] Ibid (citations omitted).

[25] Ibid 114.

[26] Ibid 115 (recommendation 8).

[27] See, eg, Automasters Australia Pty Ltd v Bruness Pty Ltd [2002] WASC 286 (Unreported, Hasluck J, 4 December 2002) [140], [148], [353] (‘Automasters’).

[28] See, eg, Kellcove Pty Ltd v Australian Motor Industries Ltd (Unreported, Federal Court of Australia, Woodward J, 6 July 1990) 139–41; Laurelmont Pty Ltd v Stockdale & Leggo (Queensland) Pty Ltd [2001] QCA 212 (Unreported, McPherson, Williams JJA and Dutney J, 5 June 2001) [46] (Dutney J).

[29] See, eg, Del Casale v Artedomus (Aust) Pty Ltd [2007] NSWCA 172; (2008) 73 IPR 326, 345 (Campbell JA).

[30] J W Carter, Elisabeth Peden and G J Tolhurst, Contract Law in Australia (5th ed, 2007) 21.

[31] [2008] NSWSC 710 (Unreported, Bergin J, 23 July 2008) [173], affd [2009] NSWCA 124 (Unreported, Tobias, Campbell and Macfarlan JJA, 28 May 2009). Contra Elisabeth Peden, ‘“Implicit Good Faith” — Or Do We Still Need an Implied Term of Good Faith?’ (2009) 25 Journal of Contract Law 50.

[32] [2004] NSWCA 15 (Unreported, Sheller, Giles and Ipp JJA, 20 February 2004) [206] (Giles JA); see also at [1] (Sheller JA), [342] (Ipp JA).

[33] Cf GEC Marconi Systems Pty Ltd v BHP Information Technology Pty Ltd [2003] FCA 50; (2003) 128 FCR 1, 208–9 (emphasis in original), where Finn J noted that ‘[t]here is not yet agreement in this country as to the province of good faith in contract law’ and that while ‘[s]ome … consider that the duty of good faith and fair dealing should apply to all contracts’, others ‘see it as a legal incident of particular classes of contract’.

[34] [1999] FCA 903; [1999] ATPR 41-703, 43 014. The recent cases which Finkelstein J regarded as making this proposition ‘clear’ were Renard Constructions (ME) Pty Ltd v Minister for Public Works (1992) 26 NSWLR 234, Hughes Aircraft Systems International v Airservices Australia [1997] FCA 558; (1997) 76 FCR 151 (‘Hughes’) and Alcatel Australia Ltd v Scarcella [1998] NSWSC 483; (1998) 44 NSWLR 349 (‘Alcatel’).

[35] [2001] NSWCA 187; (2001) 69 NSWLR 558, 573 (Sheller, Beazley and Stein JJA).

[36] [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 970, citing ibid.

[37] Burger King (Appeal) [2001] NSWCA 187; (2001) 69 NSWLR 558 was a joint judgment of Sheller, Beazley and Stein JJA. In Vodafone [2004] NSWCA 15 (Unreported, Sheller, Giles and Ipp JJA, 20 February 2004) [1] (Sheller JA), [342] (Ipp JA), Sheller and Ipp JJA agreed with the judgment of Giles JA.

[38] [2004] NSWCA 15 (Unreported, Sheller, Giles and Ipp JJA, 20 February 2004) [191] (Giles JA). His Honour was nevertheless ‘content to assume, expressly without deciding, that unless excluded by express provision or because inconsistent with the terms of the contract, Vodafone was under an implied obligation to act in good faith and reasonably in exercising its powers’ under the agreement.

[39] [2005] VSCA 228 (Unreported, Warren CJ, Buchanan JA and Osborn AJA, 15 September 2005).

[40] Meridian Retail Pty Ltd v Australian Unity Retail Network Pty Ltd [2006] VSC 223 (Unreported, Dodds-Streeton J, 21 June 2006) [205].

[41] (1977) 180 CLR 266 (Privy Council).

[42] Esso Australia [2005] VSCA 228 (Unreported, Warren CJ, Buchanan JA and Osborn AJA, 15 September 2005) [25] (Buchanan JA); see also at [1] (Warren CJ), [32] (Osborn AJA).

[43] Ibid [25] (citations omitted).

[44] See generally Gillian K Hadfield, ‘Problematic Relations: Franchising and the Law of Incomplete Contracts’ (1990) 42 Stanford Law Review 927; Andrew Terry, ‘Franchising, Relational Contracts and the Vibe(2005) 33 Australian Business Law Review 289.

[45] Esso Australia [2005] VSCA 228 (Unreported, Warren CJ, Buchanan JA and Osborn AJA, 15 September 2005) [4].

[46] (2002) 186 ALR 289, 327 (Callinan J).

[47] Ibid 311–12 (citations omitted).

[48] Ibid 312 (citations omitted).

[49] See generally Hadfield, above n 44; Terry, above n 44; Bill Dixon, ‘Common Law Obligations of Good Faith in Australian Commercial Contracts — A Relational Recipe’ (2005) 33 Australian Business Law Review 87.

[50] Bobux Marketing Ltd v Raynor Marketing Ltd [2001] NZCA 348; [2002] 1 NZLR 506, 516–17 (Thomas J) (‘Bobux’), adopted in Gough & Gilmour Holdings Pty Ltd v Caterpillar of Australia Ltd [No 11] [2002] NSWIRComm 354 (Unreported, Boland J, 19 December 2002) [54]. Thomas J was dissenting: see Bobux [2001] NZCA 348; [2002] 1 NZLR 506, 508, 518.

[51] Hadfield, above n 44, 984.

[52] Terry, above n 44.

[53] Veronica L Taylor, ‘Contracts with the Lot: Franchises, Good Faith and Contract Regulation’ [1997] New Zealand Law Review 459, 467.

[54] Ibid 466.

[55] Ibid.

[56] Hadfield, above n 44, 928.

[57] Elizabeth Crawford Spencer, Submission No 39 to Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Inquiry into Franchising Code of Conduct, 2 September 2008, 9–12.

[58] Hadfield, above n 44, 929 (citations omitted).

[59] (1993) 45 FCR 84, 97.

[60] Carter, Peden and Tolhurst, above n 30, 21.

[61] Elisabeth Peden, Good Faith in the Performance of Contracts (2003) 170 (citations omitted).

[62] [2008] NSWSC 710 (Unreported, Bergin J, 23 July 2008) [174]. See also Vodafone [2004] NSWCA 15 (Unreported, Sheller, Giles and Ipp JJA, 20 February 2004) [191] (Giles JA).

[63] See Peden, Good Faith in the Performance of Contracts, above n 61, 139–41.

[64] (1881) 6 App Cas 251, 263.

[65] (1896) 7 QLJ 68, 70–1.

[66] [1888] UKLawRpCh 64; (1888) 38 Ch D 295, 312.

[67] (1975) 30 P & CR 182, 186.

[68] [1988] 1 EGLR 264, 267, quoted in Secure Parking (WA) Pty Ltd v Wilson [2008] WASCA 268 (Unreported, Martin CJ, Buss JA and Murray AJA, 19 December 2008) [95] (Buss JA) (‘Secure Parking’). This principle was applied by the House of Lords in British Leyland Motor Corporation Ltd v Armstrong Patents Co Ltd [1986] AC 577, 643 (Lord Templeman), a case which concerned the reliance on copyright in car parts to prevent purchase of replacement parts from other vendors. In Secure Parking [2008] WASCA 268 (Unreported, Martin CJ, Buss JA and Murray AJA, 19 December 2008) [96], Buss JA documents the recent course of the principle at the level of the High Court of Australia:

In Concrete Pty Ltd v Parramatta Design & Developments Pty Ltd [(2006) [2006] HCA 55; 229 CLR 577] …, Kirby and Crennan JJ applied the doctrine of non-derogation from grant in the context of copyright licensing [at 606–7] … By contrast, Gummow ACJ reserved for further consideration any application of that doctrine in the field of copyright licensing and, also, the applicability in Australia of the reasoning in Solar Thomson Engineering Co Ltd v Barton [1977] RPC 537 and British Leyland Motor Corporation Ltd v Armstrong Patents Co Ltd [1986] AC 577. Hayne and Callinan JJ found it unnecessary to deal with the point.

[69] Jani-King (GB) Ltd v Pula Enterprises Ltd [2007] EWCA Civ 620; [2008] 1 All ER (Comm) 451, 466–7 (Judge Coulson).

[70] [2006] EWCA Civ 1209 (Unreported, Keene, Wall and Wilson LJJ, 31 August 2006) [3], [18], [20]–[23], [43]–[45] (Keene LJ).

[71] See ibid [7]–[17].

[72] Ibid [57]; see also at [60] (Wall LJ), [61] (Wilson LJ). The franchisor’s e-commerce system had a different brand name, and the prices for work that originated from this e-commerce system were fixed by the franchisor (on its website); the prices for other customers were set by the franchisee itself: at [3], [19]–[20] (Keene LJ). The franchisor attempted to use provisions of the franchise agreement to require the franchisee to complete jobs received via the e-commerce system and to promote the e-commerce brand above the original (non e-commerce) brand: at [22].

[73] [2008] FCA 867; (2008) 78 IPR 319. Apart from being mentioned in passing in Far Horizons Pty Ltd v McDonald’s Australia Ltd [2000] VSC 310 (Unreported, Byrne J, 18 August 2000) (‘Far Horizons’), the concept of non-derogation from grant has not arisen in Australian franchising cases involving good faith. In Far Horizons, at [128] (citations omitted), Byrne J stated that:

The contractual terms [sought to be implied by the franchisee] … appear to be manifestations of the general obligation imposed on a party to a contract ‘to do all the things as are necessary on his part to enable the other party to have the benefit of the contract’ and not to do anything which will derogate from the benefit of the contract.

[74] Squires Loft [2008] FCA 867; (2008) 78 IPR 319, 326 (Finkelstein J).

[75] Ibid.

[76] Ibid 327.

[77] Ibid. Interestingly, the non-derogation from grant doctrine does not seem to have been raised by the parties but by Finkelstein J, who stated: ‘Harold and Saul [the directors of the licensee] have not sought relief based on the rule that a person may not derogate from his grant. Were they to apply to amend their cross-claim to include relief in that regard I would accede to the application.’

[78] (2003) 64 OR (3d) 533, 555–6 (Weiler JA for Weiler, Austin and Laskin JJA), quoting P D Finn, ‘The Fiduciary Principle’ in T G Youdan (ed), Equity, Fiduciaries and Trusts (1989) 1, 4.

[79] (1992) 26 NSWLR 234, 265.

[80] Cf Australian Competition and Consumer Commission v C G Berbatis Holdings Pty Ltd (2003) 214 CLR 51 in relation to s 51AA of the Trade Practices Act 1974 (Cth), which does operate upon such principles.

[81] See generally Senate Standing Committee on Economics, Parliament of Australia, The Need, Scope and Content of a Definition of Unconscionable Conduct for the Purposes of Part IVA of the Trade Practices Act 1974 (2008), which addressed difficulties surrounding the definition of unconscionability.

[82] [2000] FCA 1365; (2000) 104 FCR 253, 270 (Sundberg J).

[83] See, eg, Alcatel [1998] NSWSC 483; (1998) 44 NSWLR 349, 368 (Sheller JA), citing Pierce Bell Sales Pty Ltd v Frazer [1973] HCA 13; (1973) 130 CLR 575, 587 (Barwick CJ):

If a contract confers power on a contracting party in terms wider than necessary for the protection of the legitimate interests of that party, the courts may interpret the power as not extending to the action proposed by the party in whom the power is vested or, alternatively, conclude that the powers are being exercised in a capricious or arbitrary manner or for an extraneous purpose, which is another was [sic] of saying the same thing. Thus, a vendor may not be allowed to exercise a contractual power where it would be unconscionable in the circumstances to do so …

Hasluck J in Automasters [2002] WASC 286 (Unreported, Hasluck J, 4 December 2002) [372] also seems to equate the two concepts:

The law does not prescribe a precise meaning of the term ‘good faith’ and it is probably no more than a prohibition on acting unconscionably. In that respect it is significant that s 51AC of the Trade Practices Act refers to the requirement for both parties to act in good faith in their dealings with each other.

[84] Trade Practices Act 1974 (Cth) s 51AC(3)(k).

[85] Trade Practices Act 1974 (Cth) s 51AC(3).

[86] Justice James Douglas, ‘Exploring the Recent Uncertainty Surrounding the Implied Duty of Good Faith in Australian Contract Law: The Duty to Act Reasonably — Its Existence, Ambit and Operation’ (Paper presented at the LexisNexis Contract Law Master Class, Brisbane, 24 August 2006) [40], quoting and translating Jacques-Henri Michel, ‘Brève postface en guise d’introduction’ in Centre de Recherches en Histoire du Droit et des Institutions, Facultés universitaries Saint-Louis Bruxelles, La bonne foi (1998) vii, x.

[87] Robert S Summers, ‘“Good Faith” in General Contract Law and the Sales Provisions of the Uniform Commercial Code(1968) 54 Virginia Law Review 195, 206.

[88] Jobern Pty Ltd v BreakFree Resorts (Victoria) Pty Ltd [2007] FCA 1066; [2008] Aust Contract Reports 90-269, 90 211 (Gordon J) (‘Jobern’).

[89] Hughes [1997] FCA 558; (1997) 76 FCR 151, 193 (Finn J); see also at 191–2.

[90] See below Part IV(H).

[91] Jobern [2007] FCA 1066; [2008] Aust Contract Reports 90-269, 90 211 (Gordon J) (citations omitted).

[92] Peden, Good Faith in the Performance of Contracts, above n 61, 120–1.

[93] [2006] FCA 472; (2006) 230 ALR 437, 498 (‘Goldspar’); see also at 499.

[94] Jeannie Marie Paterson, ‘Good Faith in Commercial Contracts? A Franchising Case Study’ (2001) 29 Australian Business Law Review 270, 273.

[95] [2003] 1 AC 469, 515.

[96] Summers, above n 87, 199–207.

[97] Ibid 196 (citations omitted).

[98] See ibid 203.

[99] [2007] FCA 1066; [2008] Aust Contract Reports 90-269, 90 212 (emphasis in original) (citations omitted).

[100] See ibid 90 213.

[101] Michael G Bridge, ‘Does Anglo-Canadian Contract Law Need a Doctrine of Good Faith?’ (1984) 9 Canadian Business Law Journal 385, 398.

[102] Justice Robert McDougall, ‘The Implied Duty of Good Faith in Australian Contract Law’ [2006] AUConstrLawNlr 36; (2006) 108 Australian Construction Law Newsletter 28, 33, raises another weakness — that the bad faith approach effectively requires intention:

It is plain that a failure to cooperate in achieving the contractual aim may be caused by oversight rather than intent; but only in the latter case would bad faith be arguable. Bad faith is but one of the causes of want of good faith. And bad faith may impeach the exercise of a contractual power that is not conditioned by, or subject to, an obligation of good faith in connexion with its exercise.

[103] An example of this comes from Hungry Jack’s Pty Ltd v Burger King Corporation [1999] NSWSC 1029 (Unreported, Rolfe J, 5 November 1999) [686] (‘Burger King (Trial)’), where Rolfe J states that, in acting dishonestly by failing to advise its master franchisee (Hungry Jack’s) that a high ranking manager was breaching his fiduciary duties to the company, the franchisor (Burger King) had ‘breached the implied terms of reasonableness and good faith’.

[104] [1999] NSWSC 996; (1999) 153 FLR 236, 262 (emphasis added).

[105] [2008] NSWSC 710 (Unreported, Bergin J, 23 July 2008) [178].

[106] Garry Rogers [1999] FCA 903; [1999] ATPR 41-703, 43 014 (Finkelstein J).

[107] See, eg, ibid; Bamco Villa Pty Ltd v Montedeen Pty Ltd [2001] VSC 192 (Unreported, Mandie J, 20 June 2001) [190]; Far Horizons [2000] VSC 310 (Unreported, Byrne J, 18 August 2000) [130]; Renard (1992) 26 NSWLR 234, 268 (Priestley JA).

[108] [1989] 1 QB 433, 439 (emphasis added), quoted in Paul Steinberg and Gerald Lescatre, ‘Beguiling Heresy: Regulating the Franchise Relationship’ (2004) 109 Penn State Law Review 105, 291.

[109] Bridge, above n 101, 407.

[110] Steven J Burton, ‘Breach of Contract and the Common Law Duty to Perform in Good Faith’ (1980) 94 Harvard Law Review 369, 369.

[111] See ibid 373, 377–8.

[112] Burger King (Trial) [1999] NSWSC 1029 (Unreported, Rolfe J, 5 November 1999) [508]–[554].

[113] Ibid [18].

[114] [2006] VSC 223 (Unreported, Dodds-Streeton J, 21 June 2006) [212].

[115] See above Part III(B).

[116] Overlook [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 970 (Barrett J).

[117] See, eg, Automasters [2002] WASC 286 (Unreported, Hasluck J, 4 December 2002) [353].

[118] Ibid [351].

[119] Overlook [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 970 (Barrett J).

[120] Byrne v Australian Airlines Ltd (1995) 185 CLR 410, 450 (McHugh and Gummow JJ) (‘Byrne’), quoted in ibid.

[121] Overlook [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 970 (Barrett J). See, eg, Mason v Freedman [1958] SCR 483, cited in Shelanu (2003) 64 OR (3d) 533, 556 (Weiler JA for Weiler, Austin and Laskin JJA).

[122] Shelanu (2003) 64 OR (3d) 533, 540 (Weiler JA for Weiler, Austin and Laskin JJA).

[123] Garry Rogers [1999] FCA 903; [1999] ATPR 41-703, 43 014 (Finkelstein J).

[124] [2000] VSC 310 (Unreported, Byrne J, 18 August 2000) [117].

[125] Ibid [130].

[126] See ibid. See below n 182 and accompanying text.

[127] [2001] QCA 212 (Unreported, McPherson, Williams JJA and Dutney J, 5 June 2001) [43]–[44].

[128] Ibid [43] (Dutney J), quoting Laurelmont Pty Ltd v Stockdale & Leggo (Queensland) Pty Ltd (Unreported, Queensland District Court, Dodds DCJ, 2 May 2000) [31].

[129] [2001] NSWCA 187; (2001) 69 NSWLR 558, 573 (Sheller, Beazley and Stein JJA).

[130] [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 970, quoting Byrne (1995) 185 CLR 410, 450 (McHugh and Gummow JJ).

[131] Hadfield, above n 44, 983.

[132] Overlook [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 971.

[133] See Hadfield, above n 44, 943.

[134] Ibid.

[135] [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 972.

[136] See Hadfield, above n 44, 985–6.

[137] At the conclusion of his seminal paper, Summers, above n 87, 263 (citations omitted), posed the rhetorical question: ‘Can you say what [good faith] is?’ He answered it thus:

In most cases the party acting in bad faith frustrates the justified expectations of another. As I have tried to show, the ways in which he may do this are numerous and radically diverse. Moreover, whether an aggrieved party’s expectations are justified must inevitably vary with attendant circumstances. For these reasons it is not fruitful to try to generalize further … Besides, any general definition of good faith, if not vacuous, is sure to be unduly restrictive, especially if cast in statutory form.

[138] Overlook [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 971. Overlook was a provider of television content to Foxtel, which Foxtel onsold to customers as add-on channels: at 91 957, 91 959. Without warning, Foxtel reduced by approximately half the amount it charged for the add-on channels provided by Overlook, which had the effect of reducing Overlook’s returns: at 91 959. Overlook argued that this constituted a breach of an implied obligation of good faith by Foxtel: at 91 972.

[139] A F Mason, ‘Contract, Good Faith and Equitable Standards in Fair Dealing’ (2000) 116 Law Quarterly Review 66, 75.

[140] Burger King (Trial) [1999] NSWSC 1029 (Unreported, Rolfe J, 5 November 1999) [275]–[346].

[141] Ibid [292].

[142] Joel Iglesias, ‘Applying the Implied Covenant of Good Faith and Fair Dealing to Franchises’ (2004) 40 Houston Law Review 1423, 1450 (citations omitted).

[143] Terry, above n 44, 299.

[144] Bridge, above n 101, 400.

[145] (1992) 26 NSWLR 234, 268. See generally Tyrone M Carlin, ‘The Rise (and Fall?) of Implied Duties of Good Faith in Contractual Performance in Australia’ [2002] UNSWLawJl 4; (2002) 25 University of New South Wales Law Journal 99.

[146] Renard (1992) 26 NSWLR 234, 271.

[147] Dixon, ‘Can the Common Law Obligation of Good Faith Be Contractually Excluded?’, above n 6, 113 (citations omitted).

[148] Ibid 120 (citations omitted).

[149] [1889] UKLawRpKQB 127; (1889) 23 QBD 598, 620.

[150] [1999] FCA 903; [1999] ATPR 41-703, 43 014.

[151] Far Horizons [2000] VSC 310 (Unreported, Byrne J, 18 August 2000) [120].

[152] Peden, Good Faith in the Performance of Contracts, above n 61, 176.

[153] Ibid.

[154] (1992) 26 NSWLR 234, 265.

[155] [2001] NSWCA 187; (2001) 69 NSWLR 558, 570 (Sheller, Beazley and Stein JJA).

[156] Jane Stapleton, ‘Good Faith in Private Law’ (1999) 52 Current Legal Problems 1, 8.

[157] [2007] HCA 61; (2007) 233 CLR 115, 148.

[158] This is the wording of the New Brunswick statute: Franchises Act, SNB 2007, c F-23.5, s 3(1). The Prince Edward Island statute is almost identical: see Franchises Act, RSPEI 1988, c F-14.1, s 3(1). The Alberta and Ontario statutes are similarly worded: see Franchises Act, RSA 2000, c F-23, s 7; Arthur Wishart Act (Franchise Disclosure), SO 2000, c 3, s 3(1).

[159] See Uniform Law Conference of Canada, Uniform Franchises Act (2005) ss 3(1), (3) <http://www.ulcc.ca/en/us/uniform_franchises_act_en.pdf> .

[160] Franchises Act, SNB 2007, c F-23.5, s 3(3)(a); Arthur Wishart Act (Franchise Disclosure), SO 2000, c 3, s 3(3); Franchises Act, RSPEI 1988, c F-14.1, s 3(3). See generally Shannon Kathleen O’Byrne, ‘Breach of Good Faith in Performance of the Franchise Contract: Punitive Damages and Damages for Intangibles’ (2004) 83 Canadian Bar Review 431, 432–5.

[161] (2009) 55 BLR (4th) 265, [55], [78] (D M Brown J) (‘Hyundai’).

[162] NADAP, Rules for Dispute Resolution (2006) para 1(m) <http://www.aiamc.com/files/NADAP%20Renewal%202006%20-%20Rules%20-%20EN.pdf> . The Court quotes an earlier version of these rules, but the definition of ‘good faith’ has not changed: see ibid [78].

[163] Hyundai (2009) 55 BLR (4th) 265, [80] (D M Brown J).

[164] McDougall, above n 102, 36. In Burger King (Appeal) [2001] NSWCA 187; (2001) 69 NSWLR 558, 570 (Sheller, Beazley and Stein JJA), quoting Metropolitan Life Insurance Co v RJR Nabisco Inc, 716 F Supp 1504, 1517 (Walker J) (citations omitted) (SDNY, 1989), the NSW Court of Appeal accepted that as ‘was explained in Metropolitan Life … “the implied covenant will only aid and further the explicit terms of the agreement and will never impose an obligation ‘which would be inconsistent with other terms of the contractual relationship’.”’ Similarly, in Central Exchange Ltd v Anaconda Nickel Ltd (2002) 26 WAR 33, 52 (‘Central Exchange’), quoting Kham & Nate’s Shoes No 2 Inc v First Bank of Whiting, 908 F 2d 1351, 1357 (7th Cir, 1990) (Easterbrook J for Wood, Easterbrook and Eschbach JJ), Steytler J of the Full Court of the Supreme Court of Western Australia accepted that the ‘principles of good faith “do not block [the] use of terms that actually appear in the contract”’. See also Central Exchange (2002) 26 WAR 33, 36 (Malcom CJ), 39 (Wallwork J).

[165] (2007) 63 ACSR 1, 148–9, citing Vodafone [2004] NSWCA 15 (Unreported, Sheller, Giles and Ipp JJA, 20 February 2004) [194]–[207] (Giles JA). There, at [194], Giles JA stated: ‘It is sufficient to ask whether an implied obligation of good faith and reasonableness with the content upon which the judge rested his findings of breach is inconsistent with the terms of the contract’.

[166] [2008] NSWSC 710 (Unreported, Bergin J, 23 July 2008) [162].

[167] Ibid, quoting Alcatel [1998] NSWSC 483; (1998) 44 NSWLR 349, 368 (Sheller JA). The comments were made in relation to the duty to cooperate but are applicable to good faith in this context.

[168] [2005] FCA 1486 (Unreported, Greenwood J, 20 October 2005) [59], citing Pacific Brands Sport & Leisure Pty Ltd v Underworks Pty Ltd [2005] FCA 288; [2005] Aust Contract Reports 90-213, 88 498 (‘Pacific Brands’), where Finkelstein J, according to Greenwood J, ‘gathered together a range of cases and articles reflecting American jurisprudence’ to support this proposition.

[169] Dixon, ‘Can the Common Law Obligation of Good Faith Be Contractually Excluded?’, above n 6, 115 (citations omitted).

[170] Hart v MacDonald [1910] HCA 13; (1910) 10 CLR 417 is authority for the proposition that a whole of agreement clause will not exclude terms implied by law.

[171] See (2007) 63 ACSR 1, 148–9.

[172] [2001] FCA 334; (2001) 184 ALR 481, 571 (‘NT Power’).

[173] See ibid 568, 570–1, 574–5.

[174] [2003] FCA 50; (2003) 128 FCR 1, 209.

[175] Ibid.

[176] Peden, Good Faith in the Performance of Contracts, above n 61, 137.

[177] Ibid 137–8, quoting NT Power [2001] FCA 334; (2001) 184 ALR 481, 575 (Mansfield J). See generally Pacific Brands [2005] FCA 288; [2005] Aust Contract Reports 90-213, 88 498 (Finkelstein J).

[178] See above nn 124–6 and accompanying text.

[179] Far Horizons [2000] VSC 310 (Unreported, Byrne J, 18 August 2000) [129]–[130].

[180] Ibid [129].

[181] Ibid [130].

[182] Ibid.

[183] [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 972 (Barrett J), quoting ibid [129].

[184] Overlook [2002] NSWSC 17; [2002] Aust Contract Reports 90-143, 91 972.

[185] South Australian Report, above n 16, 55, quoted in Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, 102.

[186] [1964] USSC 164; 378 US 184, 197 (1964).

[187] Goldspar [2006] FCA 472; (2006) 230 ALR 437, 498 (Gyles J).

[188] Two possible limitations on the scope of the obligation in the form recommended by the Opportunity Not Opportunism Report are that it is an obligation of ‘good faith’ and not ‘good faith and fair dealing’, and that the obligation relates to the ‘agreement’ and not the ‘relationship’: see Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, 115 (recommendation 8).

[189] (2002) 186 ALR 289, 312.

[190] In the first case involving franchising to be considered by the High Court of Australia, Master Education Services Pty Ltd v Ketchell [2008] HCA 38; (2008) 236 CLR 101, second reading speeches and explanatory statements with respect to the introduction of the Code were highly significant: see at 110 (Gummow ACJ, Kirby, Hayne, Crennan and Kiefel JJ).

[191] Inserted by Trade Practices Amendment (Fair Trading) Act 1998 (Cth) sch 2 item 2.

[192] See generally Senate Standing Committee on Economics, above n 81.

[193] Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, 110–13.

[194] Ibid 103, quoting ACCC, Submission No 60 to Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Inquiry into Franchising Code of Conduct, September 2008, 19. A draft model amendment was included in Competitive Foods Australia, Submission No 22 to Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Inquiry into Franchising Code of Conduct, September 2008, Attachment 1, quoted in ibid 111–12:

23A Obligation to act in good faith

(1) A franchisor and a franchisee shall act towards each other in good faith in the exercise of any rights or powers arising under, or in relation to, a franchise or the renewal of a franchise.

(2) For the purposes of sub-clause (1), good faith in relation to conduct by a franchisor or a franchisee means that the party has acted:

(a) honestly and reasonably; and

(b) with regard to the interests of the other parties to the franchise,

in all the circumstances, including without limitation:

(c) the commercial and business objects of the franchise;

(d) the legitimate business interests of each of the parties, and what is reasonably necessary for the protection of those interests;

(e) the respective financial and non-financial contributions made by each of the parties to the establishment and conduct of the franchised business;

(f) the risks taken by each of the parties in the establishment and conduct of the franchised business;

(g) the alternative courses of action available to the parties in respect of the matter under consideration; and

(h) the usual practices in the industry to which the franchise relates.

[195] [2007] HCA 61; (2007) 233 CLR 115, 152.

[196] [2005] VSCA 228 (Unreported, Warren CJ, Buchanan JA and Osborn AJA, 15 September 2005) [2].

[197] Ibid [3].

[198] Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, 114–15.

[199] Ibid 103, quoting ACCC, Submission No 60 to Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Inquiry into Franchising Code of Conduct, September 2008, 19.

[200] Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, 103–4, quoting Evidence to Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, Parliament of Australia, Melbourne, 5 November 2008, 96 (Graeme Samuel, Chairman, ACCC).

[201] South Australian Report, above n 16, 55.

[202] Ibid 54; see also at 55–9. See also Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, 107.

[203] Opportunity Not Opportunism Report, above n 2, 102 (citations omitted).

[204] Australian Government, Commonwealth Government Response to the Report of the Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services Opportunity Not Opportunism: Improving Conduct in Australian Franchising (2009) <http://www.innovation.gov.au/Section/SmallBusiness/Pages/FranchisingCodeofConduct.aspx> .

[205] Australian Government, Additional Information on Franchising Code and Unconscionable Conduct Reforms (2009) 1 <http://minister.innovation.gov.au/Emerson/Documents/Additional%20information%20on%20Franchising%20Code%20and%20Unconscionable%20Conduct%20reforms.pdf> . See also ibid 13.

[206] Australian Government, Commonwealth Government Response to the Report of the Parliamentary Joint Committee on Corporations and Financial Services, above n 204, 5.

[207] Ibid 13.


AustLII: Copyright Policy | Disclaimers | Privacy Policy | Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/MelbULawRw/2009/19.html