Home
| Databases
| WorldLII
| Search
| Feedback
University of Queensland Law Research Series |
Last Updated: 7 May 2009
THE UNIVERSITY OF QUEENSLAND
LEGAL RESEARCH SERIES
MORAL CAPITAL AND COMMERCIAL SOCIETY[*]
Suri Ratnapala[†]
ABSTRACT
This paper examines the idea of moral capital in relation to commerce. Moral capital is found in the form of justice, beneficence and temperance. These concepts are explained and distinguished from related ideas of social capital and human capital. Following Hume, Smith and Hayek, the author treats justice and commerce as aspects of the same evolutionary process and challenges the traditional mistrust of commerce on moral grounds. The paper discusses the ways in which commerce strengthens morality and explains why the state can enforce justice but cannot practice or enforce beneficence without harm to justice. The discussion is concluded with some thoughts about the depletion of moral capital in rich and poor countries.
1. INTRODUCTION
Modern civilization is based on laws and other
institutions that enable individuals a large measure of freedom to seek profit
through
voluntary exchange. Indeed, but for the prospect of making profits, many
transactions simply would not occur and we would denied,
most of the goods and
services that we take for granted. There is not much argument these days about
the role of profits in the production
of goods and services. Yet, the notion of
profiting from dealings with others seems intuitively wrong to many people even
when profits
are gained by perfectly legal transactions. Greeks had their own
pejorative term for money making - ‘chrematistics’.
Cicero thought
that those who buy from merchants in order to re-sell immediately make no profit
‘without much outright lying’.
(Finley, 1988: 1, 421) Some
religions still condemn usury and philosophers still pursue the quest begun by
Aristotle for the ‘just
price’. In the present age, the bias
against commerce persists, evidenced by constant pressures in democracies to
restrain
profit seeking and to redistribute wealth. There is an inarticulate
assumption in such thinking that entrepreneurship is a necessary
evil whose
consequences need to be mitigated.
There is another way of looking at human
affairs that regards commerce as not only morally unimpeachable but also
unsustainable without
moral capital. This viewpoint is closely but not
exclusively associated with the evolutionary tradition in social science that
sees
both markets and morals as aspects of the spontaneous order of society. My
aim is to examine the connections among moral capital,
commerce and economic
performance from this theoretical perspective. I argue following Adam Smith,
David Hume and later evolutionist
thinkers that commerce co-evolves with moral
rules and leads not only to prosperity but also to the accumulation of moral
capital.
Conversely depletion of moral capital can result in economic
deterioration causing further moral decline. I do not undertake the
tasks of
devising ways to measure moral capital or of empirically testing the theory, but
set myself the more modest aim of explaining
the theory by clarifying some of
the conceptual issues relevant to its understanding. The discussion intends to
provoke thoughts
on what societies can do to enhance their stocks of moral
capital.
Part 2 of this paper is a discussion of the concept of moral
capital. It explains the sense in which the disposition to moral conduct
represents a type of capital and distinguishes the concept of moral capital from
the related ideas of social capital and human capital.
The main forms of
morality are identified as justice and beneficence and temperance and it is
argued that while morality in all forms
is conducive to commerce, justice is of
special significance. A discussion of the abstract qualities of justice is
followed by an
inquiry concerning the rules of justice that are indispensable
for commerce. The part concludes with observations on the role of
institutions
in the accumulation of moral capital. Part 3 of the paper makes a closer
examination of the interconnection of commerce
and morals. Morals rules and
commerce are presented as aspects of the same evolutionary phenomenon. The
dependence of commerce on
moral capital is examined against the converse
proposition that commerce promotes greed and hence causes moral decline. Part 4
discusses
the competence of the state with respect to the accumulation of moral
capital and proposes that the state is effective mainly in
the promotion of
justice and that attempts to promote beneficence and other virtues invariably
results in the erosion of justice.
Part 5 summarises the principle conclusions
of this study and presents some thoughts about ways to build moral capital.
2. THE CONCEPT OF MORAL CAPITAL
Morality as a factor in production may be counter-intuitive but it is both
real and substantial. The most obvious ways in which morality
helps production
and exchange is by enhancing the security of person and property and by
promoting the keeping of contracts. Laws
that protect person and property and
enforce contracts are based on ubiquitous moral rules whose origins are lost in
the mists of
time. Legal re-enactment strengthens these rules but obscures their
origins. Such re-enactments are of limited value unless most
members of the
community live voluntarily by the morals that they encapsulate.
Capital
generally understood consists of resources owned by individuals or firms that
are applied in the production of goods and services.
These include incorporeal
assets such as goodwill, trade reputation and training. More recently, the
concept of capital has been
extended to conditions that help production by
facilitating coordination among parties to transactions. This form of capital
may
or may not be ‘owned’ by individuals or firms but it provides
them with clear advantages. Morality falls within this
extended meaning of
capital.
Morality as capital may be seen from the viewpoints of the
individual and of society generally. It can take two forms from the individual
standpoint. A person who is habitually moral in conduct may gain a reputation of
trustworthiness that induces others to deal with
her. This form of capital may
increase in value where institutions have become unreliable and people seek
reliable trading partners.
Again a person living in a community of individuals
who habitually observe a common set of known moral rules will have reduced costs
of transacting with others. These costs include costs of finding reliable
trading partners and costs of enforcement through self-help
or third party
intervention, in the event of breach of obligation. On the contrary, a person
living among rule breakers needs to
take costly precautions and will have to
limit his transactions to a minimum. The cost saving that accrues to a person
as a result
of the moral conduct of others represents part of the moral capital
of that person.
In what sense does a group possess moral capital? The
number and types of transactions that occur are influenced by transaction costs
(Coase, 1960; Calabresi, 1968). The extent to which the moral rules of a group
reduce transaction costs and hence facilitate mutually
advantageous dealings
between group members and between group members and outsiders represents the
community’s moral capital.
It simply means that members of the group have
an economic advantage resulting from the objective prevalence of certain moral
rules.
As explained presently, these rules owe their existence to the moral
conduct of individuals.
If capital is taken to mean a factor in the
production of goods and services, those moral rules that increase transaction
costs do
not generate moral capital. Thus, the rule against usury will not
constitute moral capital. In our tribal past it was considered
perfectly moral
to treat strangers harshly and to take forcibly their belongings and even their
lives. Coincidentally, it was a time
when we were very poor and our own lives
were, as Hobbes famously described, ‘nasty brutish and short’.
Fortunately,
we learned to extend to countless strangers some of the
consideration that previously we accorded only to our own and thereby made
civilization possible.
Moral capital distinguished from social capital
The concept of social capital refers to informal or voluntary social organisations and networks that engage in charitable activities or the production of public goods. The term ‘social capital’ in this sense is aligned to the concept of civil society, the base structure of society that is distinguishable from the coercive order imposed by the state. It is widely used in the analysis of social factors that help or hinder communities in achieving prosperity. Among the better known studies of social capital are those of Robert Putnam on the role of civic tradition in Italian democracy (Putnam 1993); Glenn Loury and Ivan Light on racial income differences (Loury 1977, Light 1972); James Coleman on the creation of human capital (Coleman 1988); and Jane Jacobs on the role of community networks in crime prevention (Jacobs 1961). In contrast, moral capital refers to individual conduct. Clearly individuals make up social networks and hence moral capital is required for social capital formation. Conversely, social networks place constraints on individual behaviour and hence contribute to moral capital. However, it is useful to distinguish these concepts not only because they are not co-extensive but also because moral capital raises distinct issues the discussion of which would not be helped by its confusion with social capital.
Human capital, work ethics and moral capital
Moral capital and human capital overlap at margins but the concepts are clearly and usefully distinguished. Human capital is regarded as the stock of skills and knowledge gained by education, training and experience that enhance a person’s earning powers and which increases the efficiency of economic decision-making. (Rosen 1998: 2, 682) Earning power arises through improved employability specific to oneself (as in self-employment), a firm or on the more general scale. (Becker 1964) Sound professional education encompasses the ethical norms relevant to the profession, such as legal ethics and medical ethics. Membership of certain guilds and tradesmen’s associations also require competencies that include knowledge of relevant ethics. Thus, training can generate moral capital. Yet, moral capital is a wider concept. Its reaches beyond the needs of specific professions or occupations and its accumulation depends on many more factors than education. Work ethics also overlaps with moral capital to the extent that it translates to just conduct or beneficence. Thus, diligence in the discharge of contractual obligations is just conduct and delivering more than what is bargained for amounts to beneficence.
Moral capital consists of justice, beneficence and temperance
Morality is conceived in both negative and positive
terms. In simple terms morality consists of ‘dos and don’ts’.
It consists on the negative side of the observance of rules forbidding certain
types of action and on the positive side of exhortations
to engage in virtuous
acts. The more important rules on the negative side have been termed rules of
justice (Hume 1964: II, 180;
Smith 1976: 79), rules of just conduct (Hayek 1982:
II, 31-33), and the morality of duty (Fuller 1964: 5-6). These are rules that
guide conduct of persons in relation to others. Many of them are formally
recognised as laws and are often coercively enforced. Some
rules like those
against unjustified killing, wilful or negligent harm to person and property,
and the breaking of promises are ubiquitous.
It seems logically impossible to
achieve harmonious coordination of the lives of a multitude without these rules.
There is also a category of negative norms that commend self-restraint even
when conduct does not directly harm others. These may
be categorised as rules of
temperance. Temperance here is not used in Plato’s sense of cardinal
virtue, but in the sense of
the social unacceptability of excessive indulgence
in pleasurable activities that are perfectly legal. Social disapprobation of
conduct
such as immodesty, alcoholism, and promiscuity offer evidence of such
rules. The types of conduct that these rules seek to curb
may be mildly
offensive to others but they do not harm them in the way unjust acts do.
Temperance as moral capital is difficult to
assess because it is a very relative
concept. One man’s moderation in drink may be another man’s excess.
Conduct appropriate
to one circumstance may be intemperate in another. Sometimes
calculated intemperance may be an advantage as when disorderly conduct
on stage
enhances the entertainment value of a rock concert. Yet, it is apparent that in
the commercial world where agents seek reliable
trading partners, reputation for
temperance will count for something.
Apart from these negative constraints,
morality in the traditional sense also encompasses positive virtue that Hume and
Smith called
beneficence (Smith 1976: 78-79) and Fuller termed the morality of
aspiration (Fuller1964: 5-6). Justice or morality of duty is expected
of us. We
will be condemned if we murder, rape or steal, but will not be praised if we
don’t. On the contrary, beneficence
or morality of aspiration is not
mandatory. We are not condemned if we fail to perform acts of great charity or
make heroic sacrifices,
but will be praised if we do. Beneficence, by this
definition, consists of voluntary acts where both the giver and the beneficiary
are not compelled to give or to receive. One can be just without being
beneficent. As Smith wrote ‘we may often fulfil all
the rules of justice
by sitting still and doing nothing’. (Smith 1976: 82) This is not to say
that beneficence carries no reward.
Its payoff can be in the form of
psychological fulfilment, reciprocal beneficence, and enhanced reputation that
fosters trust in
future dealings. Society also benefits from beneficence to the
extent that it promotes trust and eases dependence on the state.
Justice as moral capital excludes distributive justice
The term ‘justice’ is used in a specific
sense. Following a long tradition in moral philosophy, I regard justice as
pertinent
not to states of affairs but to the conduct of responsible agents that
affect others. It is justice in this sense that constitutes
moral capital. There
are other conceptions of justice including that of distributive or social
justice. Since words have no transcendentally
true meanings but only meanings
that they acquire by convention or definition, it is not possible to deny the
term ‘justice’
to such notions. However, as presently explained
distributive or social justice does not form moral capital in the economic
sense.
Moral capital excludes Aristotle’s distributive justice that
requires the division riches, honours and burdens in proportion
to each
person’s merit such as freeman status, nobility or excellence. (Aristotle,
1980: Bk 5 Ch 2, 3) It also excludes the
modern concept of social justice.
Aristotle’s distributive justice arises among persons who have claims to a
particular good
or who have suffered a particular loss, the question being how
the benefit or loss must be apportioned. Modern social justice in
contrast, is
regarded as ‘an attribute which “actions” of society, or the
“treatment” of individuals
and groups by society, ought to
possess’. (Hayek 1982: 2, 62. In my view there is no better explanation of
the notion of justice
as used herein than Hayek’s profound exposition in
chapter 8 of this work.) In this conception, responsibility is attached
to
society as a whole to produce ‘just’ distributions of wealth where
necessary overcoming conditions for which no individual,
group or government is
directly responsible. It is the old idea of distributive justice applied on the
social scale.
There are a number of considerations for excluding these two
notions of justice from the concept of moral capital. It is well to remember
why
morality is considered as capital at all. The prevalence of moral conduct on the
part of members of a community reduces the costs
of transacting in that
community. The critical factor here is the conduct of agents, not their material
resources. Wealth distribution
may create capital in some at the expense of
others, but that is not moral capital. Distributive or social justice does not
pre-announce
rules that guide future conduct. This form of justice is achieved
by retrospective adjustment of the material positions of individuals
according
to criteria such as strict equality, resource equality, utilitarianism and just
desert. They are all what Robert Nozick
calls end-state principles of justice.
(Nozick 1988: 155) Authorities who determine particular distributions of
utilities have no
way of knowing whether the distributions are just without
knowing the circumstances of every individual affected by the scheme, which
circumstances, of course, are ever changing. As John Rawls puts it, ‘the
principles of justice do not select specific distributions
of desired things as
just, given the wants of particular persons. This task is abandoned as mistaken
in principle, and it is, in
any case, not capable of a definite answer’.
(Rawls: 1963: 202)
But I exclude Rawls’ own theory for much the same
reasons. Rawls opts for a conception of justice that lays down the ground
rules
of a just political order, with justice being equated to fairness. He seeks to
elevate distributive justice to a higher level
of abstraction by proposing that
‘social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: They are
to attach to positions
and offices open to all under conditions of fair equality
of opportunity; and (b), they are to be to the greatest benefit of the
least
advantaged members of society’. (Rawls 1993: 5-6)This so-called
‘difference principle’ remains one that
demands retrospective
adjustment of material conditions not only to uphold the second limb of the
principle but also to ensure that
persons have ‘fair equality of
opportunity’ to seek positions and offices. Rawl’s difference
principle does not
inform individuals, groups and firms beforehand how they
should conduct themselves or more accurately how they should not. It simply
tells them that if they get too far ahead of the least advantaged, they will
suffer some unspecified deprivation. In Rawles’
scheme, the state can
discharge its responsibility for justice fully only by reactive measures as
‘impermissible’ inequalities
come to light. Justice in this sense
may equate to morality in some people’s judgment. But that is not the
point at issue.
It is not the kind of morality that can form capital in an
economic sense.
The general, negative and interpersonal character of the rules of justice
What then is the concept of justice that is relevant
to moral capital? Justice in this sense cannot be exhaustively defined. It is
not possible to know in advance all the possible sets of circumstances that will
raise a moral question. As the universe both in
its physical and cultural
dimensions is an evolving process we cannot even imagine all the kinds of
situations that in future may
call for our moral judgment. Some situations may
never arise and there are others that arise so rarely that our established moral
codes do not reveal a time-tested rule of conduct that we can rely upon. (For a
clear example see Sen, 1999: 54-55) Fortunately most
people intuitively grasp
the most important rules of moral conduct upon which civilised life depends.
These moral rules are inseparable
from civilisation as they are constitutive of
it. From the evolutionary viewpoint, they were winnowed by the winds of
experience.
As Hume observed, ‘rules of justice, like other conventional
things, such as language and currency, arise gradually, and acquire
force by a
slow progression, and by our repeated experience of the inconvenience of
transgressing it’. (Hume, 1975: 490)
Distillation through experience
is a process of generalisation or abstraction. The fruits of experience are
preserved ‘not
as a recollection of particular events, or explicit
knowledge of the kind of situation likely to occur, but as a sense of the
importance
of observing certain rules’. (Hayek, 1982: 2, 4) A rule of
conduct can be universalised only in the negative form unless the
rule relates
to a very narrow type of circumstance. It is impossible to express the rules
against murder, rape, theft, trespass,
and non-performance of contracts in
positive terms if they are to protect all persons currently living and yet to be
born. Universality
can be achieved only by the ‘Thou shall not ...’
formula. Even when it appears that a rule requires positive action,
it will be
seen on closer examination to be capable of negative formulation. The rule that
requires contracts to be performed is
a rule that prohibits actions contrary
contract. The rule that requires a surgeon to provide post-surgical care to a
patient is actually
an application of the rule against negligence measured by
the standard of care expected of a surgeon. Even in the rare cases where
the
common law imposes positive duties such as the seafarer’s duty of rescue
at sea, there is a special relationship at play
where the duty bearer is in a
unique, hence quasi-fiduciary position in relation to the beneficiary. The law
can be generalised
into the injunction: ‘Do not abandon a person whose
life uniquely depends on you, if can save him without endangering tour
own
life’.
The test of justice is not state recognition and enforcement.
Evolutionists and social anthropologists regard the rules of justice
as
pre-dating the emergence of the state. Smith finds the rules of justice
originating in the instinct of sympathy and disapprobation
of acts that offend
this instinct. Whereas absence of beneficence and of justice evokes
disapprobation, it is only unjust conduct
that brings forth the stronger feeling
for retribution. Retribution may occur without state intervention through social
or religious
pressure as in the case of ostracism, social shunning, expulsion
from associations, commercial blacklisting, excommunication, admonishment
and in
some cases through self-help measures.
Only norms that can be universalised
become recognised as rules of justice but not all such norms are so recognised.
As Hayek notes
Kant’s categorical imperative, to act only by rules that
you will apply to all (Kant, 1948) is a necessary but not sufficient
condition
of justice. (Hayek, 1982: 2, 43) The difference between justice and beneficence
is rooted in the very structure of the
evolved complex order that is society.
The rules of justice are the coordinating principles of social life without
which the social
structure collapses. They are determined by the nature of the
spontaneous order of society. The difference between rules of justice
and norms
of beneficence may be seen from another angle. Rules of justice forming the same
system are generally accommodated to each
other and hence may be enforced
without violence to one another. Rules of justice also can be enforced without
violence to beneficence
but as discussed presently beneficence cannot be
enforced without violence to justice.
Rules of justice concern a
person’s relations with others. A rule that is concerned with a thing will
be a rule of justice insofar
as it also concerns some other person. Thus, the
rules against pollution are rules of justice where they prevent harm to others.
However, the state has a history of legislating rules that prohibit conduct
where the harm to others is not clear. Examples include
prohibitions of
pornography and alcohol consumption. Strictly speaking, these are attempts to
enforce temperance than justice.
Substantive content of justice
Justice has two aspects, but like the sides of a coin
they are inseparable. One aspect is the presence of a rule and the other its
observance. Rules of justice are not corporeal things. Even the fact that a
‘rule’ is written in a book does not make
it a rule. A rule owes
its objective existence to its observance as an obligatory norm by a group of
interacting persons. Rules
of justice that pre-date legislative authority may be
regarded as spontaneously formed out of coincidence of behaviour. Once a rule
begins to crystallise, reliance upon it increases, causing it to be stabilised
as part of the overall social structure. Though the
genesis of a rule is in the
conduct of individuals, it may be some time before the members of the society
are able to articulate
the rule clearly. (Hume, 1978; 490, Smith, 1976: 159;
Ferguson, 1966: 34, 122, Campbell, 1965: 32-33; Hayek, 1982: 1, 17-19)
As
society evolves, so does its stock of moral and legal rules. Yet we notice that
all societies that extend beyond the small family
group share a set of basic
rules of just conduct. An extended society without these rules is difficult to
conceive and there is no
historical evidence that any have existed without them.
Functioning societies display what Hume termed ‘the three fundamental
laws
concerning the stability of possession, translation by consent and the
performance of promises’ (Hume 1975: 541) In legal
terms, they are the
laws that confer the right to hold property, the liberty to deal with property
as the owner pleases and the right
to have contracts performed. We must add to
this list, the rule of justice that prohibits violence to person. Hume
considered this
presupposed in the rules concerning property and contract.
Rights are meaningless without self–ownership as they exist in relation
to
persons. The first requirement of personhood is personal integrity.
The
basic rules that secure personal security, property and contractual freedom are
simple and few. (Epstein, 1995) Yet, their maintenance
depends on many other
rules and sub-rules. The rule that contracts must be observed cannot be
sustained without subsidiary rules
concerning misrepresentation and fraud,
mistakes, frustration, quantification of damages and importantly, the rule of
justice that
in disputes one does not judge one’s own cause but accepts
the judgment of an impartial arbiter. J S Mill considered impartiality
as a
distinguishing characteristic of justice. (Mill, 1998: 90) Contracts are
unlikely to take place where these complimentary rules
of justice are
unobserved. Similarly property is secured by the rules against theft, trespass
and other willful and negligent acts
that cause damage to property. Thus, it is
evident that rules of justice do not exist in isolation but only as parts of an
interlocking
and interacting system of rules. They include rules that secure
just conduct on the part of parties to disputes and those who assist
in the
resolution of disputes such as judges and police (public or private) and
lawyers. What is critical for justice is that the
rules are complimentary and in
harmony. Thus, just conduct on the part of a judge qua judge would consist of
upholding the rules
of justice as they apply to the case. A judge who seeks to
decree contrary to such rules undermines the system. Likewise legislators
who,
in the name of justice, create powers to adjust arbitrarily the consequences
that result from the application of the rules of
justice, in fact act unjustly.
Institutions and moral capital
Institutions are important in
several ways to the accumulation and retention of moral capital. Value of
morality as capital depends
on reputation for moral conduct. Since people cannot
read minds they predict behaviour through observation. In granting a loan, a
banker relies more on the customer’s credit history than on her moral
convictions. Even this kind of knowledge is unavailable
in most commercial
transactions. People live in societies of many millions of individuals and of
this multitude they have direct
and personal knowledge of only very few persons.
Yet their daily activities depend on the co-ordination of the actions of vast
numbers
of strangers. This coordination is made possible not by personal
knowledge of others but by reliance on observable constraints on
unjust conduct.
These constraints are ‘institutions’, a term used by economists to
encompass all the constraints that
give structure to social life including laws
and less formal rules such as customs, social practices, moral rules and all
forms of
self-restraints that people voluntarily assume. (North 1990: 3)
Institutions are not corporeal. They consist of patterns of action
arising from
the coincidence of the behaviour of individuals. These patterns, in turn, are
counted upon by individuals in the conduct
of their own affairs. Not all
institutions are humanly devised. Some are, to use Adam Ferguson’s
memorable epigram, ‘the
result of human action but not the execution of
any human design’. (Ferguson 1966: 122) Institutions are not independent
and
self-sustaining but exist as parts of a complex web of interacting
constraints.
Moral rules are institutions but not all institutions constitute
moral rules. Some institutions are morally neutral such as the rule
in England
that motorists must drive on the left side of the road or the rule that a
contract by postal communication is concluded
when the acceptance of the offer
is put in the post rather than when it is received. They are moral only in the
sense that they
supply a rule that allows people to coordinate their actions and
avoid conflict. In continental Europe opposite rules apply with
equally
beneficial effects. Some institutions, though regarded as moral may actually
increase transaction costs by regulating or
prohibiting particular kinds of
transactions altogether (bans on alcohol, Sunday shopping, etc.) and hence do
not help build moral
capital.
Institutions encapsulate moral capital to the
extent that they represent rules of justice or standards of beneficence.
Morality is
constitutive of these institutions for it is the coincidence of
moral conduct of individuals that creates and sustains them. Institutions
once
formed shape conduct by providing moral guidance and by signalling more clearly
the cost and benefits of the choices we make.
A rule can exist despite its
violation by individuals. Unlike physical laws, it is in the nature of human
rules that they are violated
from time to time. However, normative rules require
a critical level of observance to persist. We cannot foretell what this level
is, but we know when it is reached.
In early society, institutions were
closely aligned with moral rules. What was legally wrongful was practically
indistinguishable
from what was morally wrongful. Traces of this fusion are
found in many languages where one word continues to refer to both kinds
of
right. The Latin ‘ius’, the English
‘right’, the German ‘Recht’, the Italian
‘diritto’, the Spanish ‘derecho’ and the
Slavonic ‘pravo’ are few of the examples. (Vinogradoff, 1913:
61; Mill, 1998: 91-92) As Fritz Kern observes, ‘The medieval world was
filled
with theoretical respect for the sanctity of the law - not the prosaic,
dry, flexible, technical, positive law of today, dependent
as it is upon the
State, but for a law which was identified with the sanctity of the moral law.
(Kern 1968: 155) In times of absolute
monarchy, rulers claimed the power to make
law and did make law in derogation of the common law of the land. Yet, law
making did
not happen on the modern scale.
In modern democracies many laws
reflect distributional outcomes that result from complex public choice
processes. They are moral only
in the dubious sense that they satisfy the
demands of particular interest groups. In fact many such laws directly violate
Humean
justice concerning the security of property and the sanctity of contract.
Yet even leading legal positivists concede that a legal
system is unsustainable
unless it embodies a minimum content of morality. (Hart 1994: 193) The economic
cost of maintaining the legal
system grows in proportion to the extent that its
rules deviate from the community’s morals. Laws that give expression to
the
rules that members of a society observe as part of their traditional modes
of conduct need little enforcement. On the contrary, state
laws that that are
inconsistent with such morality entail high enforcement costs.
3. INTERDEPENDENCE OF MORALS AND COMMERCE
The discussion of morality as capital revealed the dependence of commerce on morality. The converse proposition that morality is strengthened by commerce requires further examination. In this section I argue that commerce was a major force in the emergence of the rules of justice and reject on logical and empirical grounds the common claim that commerce corrupts morals.
Co-evolution of justice and commerce
The critical role of commerce in shaping justice was first clearly perceived
by the eighteenth century evolutionist thinkers. This
breakthrough resulted from
their sceptical investigation of the nature of human knowledge and institutions
which led to the conclusion
that accumulated experience, not reason was the
source of moral rules. Given the premises that man has no foresight of the
future,
Hume argued that reason alone could never give rise to any original
idea. (Hume 1978: 157) Adam Smith found the idea that we can
derive from reason
the first principles of right and wrong to be ‘altogether absurd and
unintelligible’. (Smith 1976:
320) Adam Ferguson memorably declared that
‘every step and every movement of the multitude ... are made with equal
blindness
to the future; and nations stumble upon establishments, which are the
result of human action, but not the execution of any human
design. (Ferguson
1966: 122) Morality, from this perspective, is seen to emerge spontaneously and
unintentionally through the coincidences
of behaviour and the retention by
communities of practices that conferred upon them advantages. (Campbell 1965:
32-33) As Hume wrote,
rules of justice ‘arise gradually, and acquire force
by a slow progression and by our repeated experience of the inconvenience
of
transgressing it’. (Hume 1975: 490)
How does experience come about?
Smith maintained that human beings have ‘original passions’ that
lead to moral conduct.
Among these is sympathy or fellow feeling. He said that
‘we derive nothing from it except the pleasure of seeing it’.
(Smith
1976: 9) Yet, it is not a wholly unselfish passion. We have sympathy for others
because we need sympathy of others and hence
we try to judge others as we like
them to judge us - as impartial spectators. (Otteson 2002: 84-85) Whatever is
the nature of sympathy,
it cannot of its own force translate to moral rules.
Rules of conduct can only result from the experience of inter-action with
others.
This experience is caused by two other instincts. One is ‘the
desire for bettering our condition’ which ‘comes
with us from the
womb, and never leaves us till we go into the grave’. (Smith 1976: 341)
The instinct of self-advancement is
accompanied by another, the
‘propensity to truck, barter and exchange one thing for another’.
The division of labor arises
‘as the necessary, though very slow and
gradual consequence’ of this propensity and as not the product of human
wisdom
that foresees their great advantages. (Smith, 1981: 1, 25) Men learn the
rules of justice through experience of barter and exchange.
(Otteson 2002: 20)
It does not mean that people discovered already existing rules of justice in the
course of exchanging, for that
too is unintelligible from the evolutionary
standpoint. Rather, the rules were formed by practice and their existence and
value dawned
on people even as the rules emerged in consequence of their
practice. It is only the action of exchanging that reveals what exchange
is like
and what conditions make it work.
What would the first fumbling attempts at
exchange reveal? The first lesson must be that it is hard for a person to
exchange anything
that is not acknowledged by others as belonging to him. It is
in the interest of the party giving and of the party receiving that
the giver
has title. Thus exchange requires the stability of possessions that Hume saw as
a necessary condition of civil society.
John Locke considered the proposition
‘where there is no property there is no justice’ as certain as any
demonstration
in Euclid. (Locke, 1924: 18) The second lesson is that exchange is
possible only when promises are kept. Early trade was seriously
constrained by
lack of trust as evident from practices such as hostage taking as insurance and
face-to-face exchanges, the latter
still surviving in town bazaars and the
village fairs. In order to break out of these constraints and to transform
themselves into
civilisations, early communities had to acquire new moral
capital in the form of just treatment of strangers. (Hayek 1982: 2, 88)
Commercial societies eventually comprised many millions of individuals linked by
common rules of justice but with no personal knowledge
of each other. For this
to happen justice had to be institutionalised and commerce was the driving force
of this process. As Smith
wrote, commerce can seldom flourish long in any state
which does not enjoy regular administration of justice, ‘in which the
people do not feel themselves secure in the possession of their property, in
which the faith of contracts is not supported by law,
and in which the authority
of the state is not supposed to be regularly employed in enforcing the payment
of debts from all those
who are able to pay’. (Smith, 1976: 910)
Once
established, rules of justice continue to gain strength from commerce. Smith was
convinced of the moral superiority of the commercial
class over the landholding
feudal aristocracy. (Smith 1978: 538) He claimed that feudal landlords who
enjoyed wealth and security
by birthright had little interest in industry or
commerce and sought aggrandizement through plunder and warfare thus
‘interrupting
the regular execution of justice’. (id: 421) In
contrast, ‘Whenever commerce is introduced into any country, probity
and
punctuality always accompanied it’. (Smith 1978: 538) His explanation of
the cause of this propensity anticipated later
theory of how the problem of
defection from rules is overcome. ‘Where people seldom deal with one
another, we find that they
are somewhat disposed to cheat because they can gain
more by a smart trick than they can lose by the injury which it does to their
character ... wherever dealings are more frequent, a man does not expect to gain
so much by any one contract as by probity and punctuality’.
(ibid)
Does commerce corrupt justice?
The fact that commerce co-evolved with justice
suggests that each facilitated the growth of the other in a quasi-symbiotic
manner.
Yet, the charge is often heard that commerce creates a culture of greed
and bestows on some the bargaining power to corrupt the institutions
of justice.
The argument implies that commerce carries the seeds of its own destruction. If
it is true, it means that commerce has
become independent of justice. This is
not possible because property rights and contractual freedom are essential to
commerce and
can be secured only by justice. If justice dies, commerce dies with
it.
If commerce has an effect on the way people behave, it is through
cultural rather than biological change. If evolutionary psychology
has any
credence, commerce has not been around long enough to make changes to our
adapted minds. (Barkow et al, 1992: 3-15) Hence commerce could not have
implanted greed in the human psyche as some contend. (See for example, Booth
1994: 658)
What is not at issue is the capacity of commerce to shape customs and
institutions of people. It has also made the pursuit of profits
whether out of
greed or other impulse an acceptable form of behaviour. It does not follow
necessarily that commerce made it acceptable
to profit by unjust
conduct.
The Humean notion of justice concerning the security of person,
property and contract appears more stable in societies that have
achieved high
levels of prosperity through commerce than in societies that are biased against
commerce. Strong evidence of this
co-relation is provided by surveys such as
The Index of Economic Freedom. (Heritage Foundation/Wall Street Journal,
2003) This is hardly surprising given that commerce expands the range of
opportunities
available for persons to satisfy their needs and desires by just
means. Commerce allows me to obtain through trade things I could
only have
gained by plunder in pre-commercial society. There is no reason to think that
wealth increases incentives for unjust conduct,
particularly if the costs of
unjust conduct are high owing to effective law enforcement. It is more often the
inability of persons
to satisfy their needs and desires through just conduct
that drives them to injustice. Unjust behaviour may occur in times of extreme
scarcity. Here too commercial society has a better record of responding to
catastrophic shortages than command economies. (Sen, 1999)
Injustice in the
Humean sense is much more likely to result directly or indirectly from state
action. The state directly outlaws
just conduct and sanctions injustice by
legislation that abrogates property rights, limits contractual freedom and
displaces the
principle of fault-based liability. In weakening justice, the
state weakens commerce and further erodes justice.
Economic studies of crime
tend to attribute rising crime rates (a useful yardstick of injustice as herein
understood) to combinations
of causes such as economic decline, demographic
factors, weakening deterrence and social disruptions. (Becker, 1968, Deadman
and
MacDonald, 2002: 13; Wynarczyk, 2002: 34-35; Fukuyama, 1999: 80-85) The
state bears primary responsibility for weakening deterrence.
Official policy in
many countries even rejects deterrence as an aim of criminal justice. Social
disruption (of which drug abuse,
family break ups, single parenting, truancy,
falling school standards and welfare dependency are symptoms) is attributable to
combinations
of reasons. Yet there are persuasive studies that identify as major
causes, the perverse incentives and moral hazard created by the
welfare state
itself (Becker, 1981; Murray, 1984).
Does commerce hinder beneficence?
In contrast to his conviction that commerce was
unambiguously favourable to justice and temperance, Adam Smith was pessimistic
about
its effect on beneficence. (See discussion of Smith’s position on
this question in Rosenberg, 1990) Smith’s pessimism
was based on what he
thought were the direct and indirect negative consequences of commerce on
beneficence. The direct harm he feared
was in regard to the effect of
specialisation on the education of the working class. The indirect consequence
concerned the diminishing
opportunities for beneficence that resulted from the
strengthening of justice.
Smith thought that the division of labour had the
tendency to make some classes ‘stupid and ignorant’ as their working
lives become confined to ‘a few simple operations’. Of the man of
labour, he wrote: ‘The torpor of his mind renders
him, not only incapable
of relishing or bearing a part in any rational conversation, but of conceiving
any generous, noble, or tender
sentiment, and consequently of forming any just
judgment concerning many even of the ordinary duties of private life.’
(Smith
1976: 782) In contrast, a member of pre-commercial society was versatile,
‘capable of doing, almost every thing which any other
man does or is
capable of doing’. (id: 783) Smith’s point was that in
pre-commercial society a person had wider but shallower
knowledge while the
person in the age of specialisation had deeper knowledge over a much narrower
field. Although this specialisation
conferred tremendous advantages on human
civilisation, he feared that ‘all the nobler parts of the human character
may be,
in a great measure, obliterated and extinguished in the great body of
the people’. (id: 783-784) Smith advocated universal
education ‘for
reward so moderate that even a common labourer can afford it’. (id: 785)
The pay-off for government was
that an educated electorate would make more
mature political judgment and be less prone to manipulation by interested
faction. (id:
788)
History has shown that Smith’s fear was misplaced. To be fair to Smith, it is most unlikely that when he suggested that the ‘nobler parts of the human character’ will be debased by the type of work people do, he was thinking of changes in human nature. Smith believed that human nature was made up of certain ‘original passions’ of which one was sympathy. (Smith, 1976: 9) As mentioned before, human psychology is not malleable over the relatively short period of time in which commercial society has existed. Smith had in mind the weakening of the capacity for moral judgment as a result of lessening life experience. Smith was mistaken on this count. The division of labour has distributed wealth in ways that no one anticipated and the typical unskilled person today has much more knowledge than the typical peasant of pre-industrial society. This knowledge is imparted not only by formal education but also by the incessant transmission of information that characterises technologically advanced economies. Smith also did not foresee that modes of production that he rightly or wrongly associated with the moral decline of the working class, the large factory, the labour intensive mine and such like, would themselves be only transitory. The acute specialisation that these modes engendered are being superseded by the more general and multi-skilled attributes demanded by manufacturing, trading and service sectors of modern economies. What was missing from Smith’s calculations was the role of technological change in institutional development.
As regards the indirect effects of commerce on beneficence, Smith’s reasoning was that when justice prevails and security from violence improves, the need for communal solidarity is lessened. He thought that the decline of this interdependence would reduce opportunities for beneficence. Smith is closer to the mark here. Opportunities for beneficence are diminished when people become prosperous and secure in their personal liberties and possessions. In prosperous welfare states, this inter-dependence has been reduced by a combination of private wealth generated by commerce and state provided welfare. These conditions may make people less aware of the opportunities and needs for beneficence but it is improbable that the human capacity and propensity for beneficence has declined as a result of economic independence. Certainly, no one has produced reliable data that indicates it does. On the contrary, everything that we know about evolution tells us that if beneficence was part of human nature two hundred years ago, it must be still part of human nature. It takes much more time for environmental changes to alter human psychology. (Mithen 1996: 223) The upsurges in private aid in times of catastrophe and the large scale of private charity flowing from the rich to poor countries contradict the view that prosperity diminishes beneficence as a human quality.
4. THE STATE AND MORAL CAPITAL
Can the state be beneficent?
The state can be just by observing and
the rules of justice and by maintaining the institutions for the administration
of justice.
Can it be beneficent? The question needs to be separated from the
question whether the state can enforce beneficence on the part
of its citizens.
It must also be distinguished from the capacity of rulers to be beneficent with
their private wealth or wealth at
their disposal by virtue of constitutional
prerogative. The capacity of the state to engage in beneficence in its own right
depends
on the resources that belong to it. I cannot be beneficent by giving
away your money. Similarly it is misleading to say that the
state can be
beneficent by taking one person’s wealth to give another.
The state
can be beneficent in a meaningful sense only if it has wealth that it has not
taken coercively from citizens and does not
hold as the agent or fiduciary of
the citizens. The modern state has very little, if any, such wealth. When the
state provides public
goods out of tax revenue it acts more like a party to a
contract to provide public goods. Where the citizens agree unanimously or
according to an agreed constitutional process to authorise the state to carry
out some beneficent act on their behalf, the state
simply acts as the agent of
the public. When the state gives away public lands, it is granting lands that it
holds in trust for the
people. Even when the state acquires wealth through
commercial enterprise, it does so with capital taken from citizens. Hence,
it
is not very useful to talk of the beneficence of the state in its own right.
More pertinent is the question whether it can make
the citizens beneficent.
Can the state enforce beneficence?
Adam Smith argued that although
the absence of beneficence excites disapprobation, attempts to extort it would
be even more improper.
(Smith, 1976: 79) He wrote: ‘To neglect it
altogether exposes the commonwealth to many gross disorders and shocking
enormities,
and to push it too far is destructive of all liberty, security, and
justice. ’ (id: 81) Smith realised that while beneficence
is highly
desirable, it couldn’t be exacted without jeopardising the more
fundamental morality that is justice. Beneficence
is the ‘ornament which
embellishes’ the building whereas justice ‘is the main pillar that
upholds the whole edifice.’
(id: 86) While both justice and beneficence
form the moral capital of society, the state is effective only in the promotion
of justice.
Beneficence can only be promoted by ‘advice and
persuasion’. (id: 81)
The modern democracy typified by the OECD
countries is a welfare state that has assumed a wide range of social security
functions.
It is also characterised by direct and indirect wealth transfers
through taxation and regulation of economic activity. Coercive
wealth transfers
do not constitute acts of beneficence on the part of the state or the persons
from whom the wealth is transferred.
It can hardly be said that I engage in a
beneficent act when I give that which I am forced to giving. If I choose to
distribute
my wealth I will be beneficent but only because the rules of justice
do not require me to do so. A private citizen who coerces me
to give away my
wealth commits a serious crime. When the state compels me to part with my
wealth, it may be acting lawfully but contrary
to the rules of justice.
Most members of a society are likely to agree that every member should have
an economic safety net for coping with misfortune. There
is an element of
beneficence in such an arrangement though it is also in everyone’s self
interest as a form of universal insurance
against catastrophe. However, in the
age of democracy, the welfare state has extended itself far beyond this
objective. Elected governments,
particularly those whose powers are not
carefully circumscribed by constitutional rules, cannot ignore the
distributional claims
of critical sections of the voting public on whom its fate
depends. As Hayek wrote, ‘an omnipotent democratic government simply
cannot confine itself to servicing the agreed views of the majority of the
electorate’ but will be forced ‘to bring together
and keep together
a majority by satisfying the demands of a multitude of special interests, each
of which will consent to the special
benefits granted to other groups only at
the price of their own special interests being equally considered’. (Hayek
1982: 3,
99) The argument that wealth transfers resulting from the electoral
process and the discretionary powers of government have little
to do with
genuine collective choice is well supported by public choice studies. (Buchanan
1962, 1975, 1986; Tullock 1962, 1976;
Olsen 1965, 1982) Even if it is conceded
that such transfers deserve the name beneficence on the occasions that they
benefit the
genuinely destitute, there is no way of determining accurately, the
winners and losers in the overall political scramble. It is hard
to disagree
with Wilhelm Ropke’s comment that the welfare state has degenerated
‘into an absurd two-way pumping of money
when the state robs nearly
everybody and pays nearly everybody, so that no one knows in the end whether he
has gained or lost in
the game’. (Ropke 1971: 164-5) Indeed Brennan and
Buchanan reminds, ‘the implementation of political transfers will always
be such that the direction of transfer is away from the minority and toward the
decisive majority, and the poorest cannot be expected
to be in the decisive
majority any more often than anyone else.’ (Brennan and Buchanan 1985:
128) In the absence of genuine
community consensus, the coercive redistributions
effected in the name of social welfare transgress the rules of justice.
These
observations are not meant to understate the value of beneficence as a moral
good or as moral capital. Acts of beneficence as
herein understood benefit both
giver and recipient. They rarely have externalities if performed in accordance
with rules of justice.
As previously stated, beneficence increases trust and
reduces transaction costs. A society without beneficence will also be one where
all those in need are dependant on the state. In such a society, justice will
be in increasing jeopardy from the continual interventions
of state. A society
rich in beneficence will be more than likely a society rich in justice because
beneficence requires stability
of possessions that is only secured by justice.
State and temperance
Temperance is traditionally promoted by social disapprobation, religious beliefs and commonsense adoption out of self-interest. However, the modern state has a record of attempting to compel temperance by law. Restrictions on alcohol and tobacco sales and consumption, prohibition of many recreational drugs, regulation of prostitution, censorship of erotica are more prominent examples of temperance related limits on liberty. Legislators seek to justify these laws on grounds that they protect not only the consumer but also others. Yet they deviate radically from traditional tort principles. Tort law allows freedom of action but compels reparation if harm results from intentional or negligent conduct. It does not ban activities beforehand but lays down duties of care towards others. Modern laws that are designed to enforce temperance or abstinence prohibit activities that may never harm another. They erode justice by diminishing self-ownership, property rights and contractual freedom and impose significant costs by limiting choice. Admittedly, there are difficult issues at the edges. Pre-emptive action is necessary in the face of clear and present danger to the public but intemperance rarely poses such danger. This explains perhaps the notorious ineffectiveness of such laws.
5. CONCLUSIONS
This theoretical study has revealed that there is no
tension between morality and commerce when morality is understood as pertaining
to the conduct of human agents as distinguished from end states. On the contrary
just conduct is a necessary condition for commerce.
Justice is the foundation
of beneficence for justice alone secures personhood, property and contractual
freedom that make true beneficence
possible. The argument that commerce per
se promotes a culture of greed and hence corrupts morals is rejected on
logical grounds. It is also rejected, as Peter Bauer would
say, on the evidence
of the senses that suggests endemic corruption to be associated mostly with
poorer societies where economic
and political freedoms are severely curtailed by
state action. (Bauer, 2000:20)
There is, however, much tension between
commerce and justice when justice is understood as an end state. Social justice
is an end
state conception of justice that departs from the idea of morality as
an attribute of conduct. Social justice demands particular
patterns of wealth
distribution that can be achieved only through coercive wealth transfers. It
contradicts justice as just conduct
and unsettles the institutional framework of
commerce. End state justice is only possible through an agent with power to
continually
to make adjustments in the material condition of persons – in
a word the state. Thus, a principal conclusion from this discussion
is that the
state in its present interventionist form is a major source of injustice.
The state can contribute to the accumulation of moral capital by nurturing
and strengthening the institutions of justice. Again,
as commerce and justice
are inter-dependent, the removal of obstacles to commerce is a logical means of
promoting justice. However,
justice cannot be maintained solely by force of law.
It needs to take root in the culture of the people. In industrialised
democracies,
there has been a weakening of the culture of ‘playing by the
rules’ and as Becker, Murray, Fukuyama and others have pointed
out, much
of this is the result of misguided social re-engineering efforts. The weakening
of property rights, the undermining of
contractual certainty and the fault basis
of liability through numerous legislative interventions and discretionary powers
have not
only directly distorted rules of justice but have also lead to a
general decline of the culture of responsibility for one’s
conduct. The
extension of the welfare state beyond the safety net paradigm has been
disruptive of the traditional institutions that
nurtured the culture of justice
and beneficence such as family, church and school. Fukuyama sees in late
twentieth century statistics,
an encouraging process of social and moral
re-norming. (Fukuyama, 2000: 271). Such re-norming may prove unsustainable
without the
withdrawal of the state to a much narrower province.
The problem
of moral capital depletion is more acute in poorer nations. The institutions of
justice are weak in these countries and
commerce is greatly hampered by
arbitrariness of government, nepotism, cronyism, state patronage, excessive
regulation, lack of transparency
and accountability of public authorities, and
inherited cultural constraints on market processes. These problems will not be
overcome
without the liberalisation of their political and economic systems. As
the success of the so-called Asian Tiger nations and more
recently China have
shown, commerce can drive political and legal reform. This process can be
catalysed by the industrialised democracies
through the removal of barriers to
trade. Trade barriers limit property rights and contractual freedom of those
living at home and
abroad and hence their elimination will promote justice
everywhere.
References
Aristotle, (1980), Nicomachean Ethics, Ross D tr,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Axelrod, Robert, (1986) Evolution of Cooperation, New York: Basic Books.
Barkow, H, Cosmides, L and Tooby, J, eds, (1992), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, New York: Oxford University Press.
Bauer, P (2000), From Subsistence to Exchange and Other Essays, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Becker, G, (1964) Human Capital, New York: Columbia University Press.
Becker, G, (1968) ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, Journal of Political Economy, 76, 169-217.
Becker, G (1981), A Treatise on the Family, Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press.
Booth, W J ((1994), ‘On the idea of the moral economy’, American Political Science Review, 88, 3: 653-667.
Brennan, Geoffrey and Buchanan James M, (1985) Reason of Rules, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Buchanan, James M, (1975) The Limits of Liberty, Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Buchanan, James M and Tullock, G, The Calculus of Consent, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Buchanan, James M, (1986), Liberty Market and State, Brighton: Wheatsheaf Books.
Calabresi, G, (1968), ‘Transaction costs, resource allocation and liability rules: a comment, Journal of Law and Economics, 11: 67-73.
Campbell, D T, (1965) 'Variation and Selective Retention in Socio-Cultural Evolution', in Social Change in Developing Areas: A Reinterpretation of Evolutionary Theory, (ed Barringer H R, Blanksten G I and Mack R W), Cambridge, Mass: Schenkman.
Coase, Ronald, (1960) ‘The Problem of Social Cost’, Journal of Law and Economics 3:1-44.
Deadman D and MacDonald Z, (2002) ‘Why has crime fallen? An economic perspective’, Economic Affairs, 22:3, 5-14.
Epstein, R, (1995) Simple Rules for a Complex World, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Ferguson, A, (1966) An Essay on the History of Civil Society 1767, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Finley, M I, (1988) ‘Chrematisctics’, The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, vol 1, London and Basingstoke: Macmillan, 421-423.
Fukuyama, Francis (2000) The Great Disruption: Human Nature and the Reconstruction of Social Order, London: Profile Books.
Fuller, Lon L, (1964) The Morality of Law, New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
Hardin, Russell (1982) Collective Action, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Hart, H L A (1994) The Concept of Law 2nd ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hayek, F A, (1982) Law Legislation and Liberty, Volumes 1, 2 and 3, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Hertiage Foundation, The and The Wall Street Journal, (2003) 2003 Index of Economic Freedom, http://cf.heritage.org/index/indexoffreedom.cfm
Hume, David, (1964) Essays Moral, Political and Literary, T H Green and T H Grose eds, Darmstadt: Scientia Verlag Aalen.
Hume, David, (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hume, David, (1975) Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Jacobs, J (1961) The Death and Life of Great American Cities, New York: Vintage Books.
Kant, I (1948) Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, tr Paton H J, London: Hutchinson’s University Library.
Kern, Fritz, (1968) Kingship and Law in the Middle Ages, New York: Harper & Row.
Latham, Mark (1998) Civilising Global Capital: New Thinking for Australian Labor, Sydney: Allen & Unwin.
Light I H, (1972) Ethnic Enterprise in America, Berkeley: University of California Press.
Locke J, (1924) Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Loury G, (1977) ‘A dynamic theory of racial income differences’ in Wallace P A LeMund A eds, Women, Minorities and Employment Discrimination, Lexington, Mass: Lexington Books.
Macneil, Ian R, (1980) The New Social Contract, New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
Mandeville, Bernard, (1924) The Fable of the Bees or, Private Vices, Publick Benefits, vols 1 and 2, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Menger, Carl, (1985) Investigations into the Method of the Social Sciences with Special Reference to Economics, New York: New York University Press.
Mill, J S, (1999) Utilitarianism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mithen, Steven, (1996) The Prehistory of the Mind, London: Phoenix.
Murray, C (1984), Losing Ground, New York: Basic Books.
North, Douglass, (1990) Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nozick, R (1988), Anarchy, State and Utopia, Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd.
Olson, Mancur (1982), The Rise and Decline of Nations, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Olson, Mancur (1965), The Logic of Collective Action, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Otteson, J R (2002) Adam Smith’s Marketplace of Life, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Putnam, Robert (1993), Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rawls, J (1963), ‘Constitutional liberty and the concept of justice’, Nomos VI: Justice, New York: Atherton Press.
Rawls, J (1993) Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.
Ropke, Wilhelm (1971), A Humane Economy: The Social Framework of the Free Market, Chicago: Henry Regnery.
Rosen, S, (1988) ‘Human Capital’, The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, Vols 1-3, London: Macmillan.
Rosenberg, Nathan, (1990) ‘Adam Smith and the stock of moral capital’, History of Political Economy, 22: 1-17.
Sen, Amartya, (1999), Freedom as Development, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Smith, Adam, (1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Smith, Adam, (1978) Lectures on Jurisprudence, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Smith, Adam, (1981) An Inquiry into the Nature and
Causes of the Wealth of Nations, Vols. I and II, Indianapolis: Liberty
Classics.
Vinogradoff, Paul, (1913) Common-Sense in Law, London: Thornton Butterworths Ltd.
Wynarczyk. P, (2002) ‘Ethical limitations on criminal participation’, Economic Affairs, 22:3, 29-36.
[*]
S Ratnapala, 'Moral Capital and Commercial Society' (2003) VIII (2) The
Independent Review: A Journal of Political Economy 213-233
Sections
of this article are reprinted with permission from the publisher of The
Independent Review: A Journal of Political Economy
(Fall 2003, Volume VIII, no.
2, pp. 213-233). © Copyright 2003, The Independent Institute, 100 Swan Way,
Oakland, CA 94621-1428
USA; info@independent.org; www.independent.org
[†]Suri Ratnapala LLB (Colombo), LLM (Macquarie), PhD (Queensland); Professor of Law, T C Beirne School of Law, University of Queensland, Director, Centre for Legal and Economic Study of Institutions (CLESI) and Fellow of the International Centre for Economic Research, Turin (ICER). This paper was researched and completed during the author’s Fellowship at ICER. The author gratefully acknowledges the contributions of Professor Enrico Colombatto, Stefano Chiadò, and the Editor and anonymous referees of the Independent Review.
AustLII:
Copyright Policy
|
Disclaimers
|
Privacy Policy
|
Feedback
URL: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/UQLRS/2003/2.html